-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 13
/
Copy pathps7.tex
1864 lines (1794 loc) · 98.8 KB
/
ps7.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
%% Anti-Copyright 2015 - the scrivener
\chapter{Linearization of homotopy types (2)}
\label{ch:VII}
\presectionfill\ondate{22.10.}\pspage{555}\par
% 133
\hangsection{Birth of Suleyman.}\label{sec:133}%
Again nearly a week has passed by without writing any notes -- the
tasks and surprises of life took up almost entirely my attention and
my energy. It were days again rich in manifold events -- most
auspicious one surely being the birth, three days ago, of a little
boy, Suleyman, by my daughter. The birth took place at ten in the
evening, in the house of a common friend, in a nearby village where my
daughter had been awaiting the event in quietness. It came while
everyone in the house was in bed, the nearly five years old girl
sleeping next to her mother giving birth. The girl awoke just after
the boy had come out, and then ran to tell Y (their hostess) she got a
little brother. When I came half an hour later, the little girl was
radiant with joy and wonder, while telling me in whispers, sitting
next to her mother and to her newborn brother, what had just
happened. As usual with grownups, I listened only distractedly,
anxious as I was to be useful the best I could. There wasn't too much
by then I could do, though, as the mother knew well what was to be
done and how to do it herself -- presently, tie the chord twice, and
then cut it in-between. ``Now you are on your own, boy!'' she told him
with a smile when it was done. A little later she and Y helped the
baby to a warm bath -- and still later, while the girl was asleep next
to her brother and Y in her room, the mother took a warm bath herself
in the same basin, to help finishing with the labors. When her mother
arrived a couple of hours later, everybody in the house was asleep
except me in the room underneath, awaiting her arrival while taking
care of some fallen fruit which had been gathered that very day.
This birth I feel has been beneficial, a blessing I might say, in a
number of ways. The very first one I strongly perceived, was about
Suleyman's sister, who had so strongly participated in his birth. This
girl has been marked by conflict, and her being is in a state of
division, surely as strongly as any other child of her age. However,
after this experience, if ever her time should come to bear a child
and give birth, she will do so with joy and with confidence, with no
secret fear or refusal interfering with her labors and with the act of
giving birth -- this most extraordinary act of all, maybe, which a
human being is allowed to accomplish; this unique privilege of woman
over man, this blessing, carried by so many like a burden and like a
curse\dots\enspace And there are other blessing too in this birth
which I perceive more or less clearly, and surely others still which
escape my conscious attention.\pspage{556}
I suspect that potentially, in every single instance anew, the act of
giving birth, and the sudden arrival and presence of a newborn, are a
blessing, carry tremendous power. In many cases, however, the greatest
part (if not all) of this beneficial power is lost, dispersed through
the action of crispation and fear (including the compulsory medical
``mise en scène'', from which it gets over harder to get rid in our
well-to-do countries\dots). A great deal could be said on this matter
in general, while my own leanings at present would be, rather, to
ponder about the manifold personal aspects and meaning of the
particular, manifold event I have just been involved in. But to yield
fully now to this leaning of mine would mean to stop short with the
mathematical investigation and with these notes. The drive carrying
this investigation is very much alive, though, and I have been feeling
it was time getting back to work -- to this kind of work, I mean.
This brings me to somewhat more mundane matters -- such as the
beginning of school and teaching duties. This year I am in charge of
preparing the ``concours d'agrégation'',\scrcomment{these are the
civil service competitive examinations for high school (lycée)
teachers\dots} something which, I was afraid, would be rather
dull. Rather surprisingly, the first session of common work on a
``problème d'agrègue'' wasn't dull at all -- the problem looked
interesting, and two of the three students who turned up so far were
interested indeed, and the atmosphere relaxed and friendly. It looks
as though I was going again to learn some mathematics through
teaching, or at any rate to apply things the way I have known and
understood them (in a somewhat ``highbrow'' way, maybe) to the more
down-to-earth vision going with a particular curriculum (here the
``programme d'agrègue'') and corresponding virtuosity tests --
something rather far, of course, from my own relation to mathematical
substance! Besides these arpeggios, we started a microseminar with
three participants besides me, on the Teichmüller groupoids; I expect
one of the participants is going to take a really active interest in
the stuff. I have been feeling somewhat reluctant to start this
seminar while still involved with the homotopy story, which is going
to keep me busy easily for the next six months still, maybe even
longer. Sure enough, the little I told us about some of the structures
and operations to be investigated, while progressively gaining view of
them again after a long oblivion -- and as discovering them again
hesitatingly, while pulling them out of the mist by bribes and bits --
this little was enough to revive the special fascination of these
structures, and all that goes with them.\pspage{557} It seems to me
there hasn't been a single thing in mathematics, including
motives,\scrcomment{unreadable margin note}
which has exerted such a fascination upon me. It will be hard, I'm
afraid, to carry on a seminar on such stuff, and go on and carry to
their (hopefully happy!) end those ponderings and notes on homotopical
algebra, so-called -- and a somewhat crazy one too at times, I am
afraid! We'll see what comes out of all this! The night after the
seminar session at any rate, and already during the two hours drive
home, the Teichmüller stuff was brewing anew in my head. Maybe it
would have gone on for days, but next day already several things came
up demanding special attention, last not least being the birth of
Suleyman\dots
\bigbreak\scrcomment{the typescript says ``26.8.'' but it
must be a misprint!}
\presectionfill\ondate{26.10.}\par
% 134
\hangsection[Back to linearization in the modelizer \Cat: another
\dots]{Back to linearization in the modelizer
\texorpdfstring{\Cat}{(Cat)}: another handful of questions around
Kan-Dold-Puppe.}\label{sec:134}%
It is time to come back to the ``review'' of linearization of
(ordinary) homotopy types, and the homology and cohomology formalism
in the context of the modelizer \Cat, which has been pushed aside now
for over two months, for the sake of that endless digression on
schematization of homotopy types. The strong tie between these two
strains of reflection has been the equal importance in both of the
linearization process. Technically speaking though, linearization, as
finally handled in the previous chapter (via the so-called
``integrators''), looks pretty much different from the similar
operation in the schematic set-up, due (at least partly) to the choice
we made of models for expressing schematic homotopy types, namely
taking semisimplicial scheme-like objects; which means, notably,
working with $\Simplex$ rather than more general test categories, and
relying heavily on the Kan-Dold-Puppe relationship. In the discrete
set-up, it turned out (somewhat unexpectedly) that the latter can be
replaced, when working with more general categories $A$ than
$\Simplex$ (which need not even be test categories or anything of the
kind), by the $\mathrm Lp_!\supab$ operation (when $p:A\to e$ is the
map from $A$ to the final object $e$ in \Cat), computable in terms of
a choice of an ``integrator'' for $A$. More specifically, recalling
that
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.1}
p_!\supab : \Ahatab \to \Ab\tag{1}
\end{equation}
is defined as the left adjoint of the inverse image functor
\[p^*:\Ab\to\Ahatab,\]
associating to every abelian group the corresponding ``context''
abelian\pspage{558} presheaf on $A$, and
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.2}
\LH_\bullet = \mathrm Lp_!\supab : \D^-(\Ahatab) \to \D^-\Ab, \quad
\text{inducing $\D_\bullet(\Ahatab)\to\D_\bullet\Ab$}\tag{2}
\end{equation}
is its left derived functor (computed using projective resolution of
complexes bounded above in \Ahatab), composing \eqref{eq:134.2} with
the tautological inclusion functor
\[\Ahatab\hookrightarrow\D_\bullet(\Ahatab)\hookrightarrow
\D^-(\Ahatab),\]
we get a canonical functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.3}
\mathrm Lp_!\supab \restrto \Ahatab:\Ahatab\to \D_\bullet\Ab,\tag{3}
\end{equation}
which may be expressed in terms of an integrator $L_\bullet^B$ for
$B=A\op$, i.e., a projective resolution of the constant presheaf
$\bZ_B$ in \Bhatab, as the composition
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.4}
\Ahatab\to\Ch_\bullet\Ab\to\D_\bullet\Ab,\tag{4}
\end{equation}
where the first arrow is
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.5}
F\mapsto F *_\bZ L_\bullet^B : \Ahatab\to\Ch_\bullet\Ab,\tag{5}
\end{equation}
and the second is the canonical localization functor. The functors
\eqref{eq:134.2} and \eqref{eq:134.3} may be viewed as the (total)
homology functors of $A$, with coefficients in complexes of abelian
presheaves, resp.\ in abelian presheaves simply. When we focus
attention on the latter, we may introduce in \Ahatab{} the set of
arrows which become isomorphisms under the total homology functor
\eqref{eq:134.3}, let's call them ``\emph{abelian weak equivalences}''
in \Ahatab, not to be confused with the notion of quasi-isomorphism
for a map between complexes in \Ahatab. Let's denote by
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.6}
\HotabOf_A = (W_A\supab)^{-1}\Ahatab\tag{6}
\end{equation}
the corresponding localized category of \Ahatab, where $W_A\supab$
denotes the set of abelian weak equivalences in \Ahatab. Thus, the
choice of an integrator $L_\bullet^B$ for $A$ (i.e., a cointegrator
for $B$) gives rise to a commutative diagram of functors
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.7}
\begin{tabular}{@{}c@{}}
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base)]
\Ahatab \ar[r]\ar[d] & \Ch_\bullet\Ab\ar[d] \\
\HotabOf_A \ar[r] &
|[alias=O]| {\ooalign{$\D_\bullet\Ab$\cr$\D_\bullet\Ab\eqdef\HotabOf$\hidewidth\cr}}
\end{tikzcd}\qquad\qquad,
\end{tabular}\tag{7}
\end{equation}
where the lower horizontal arrow is defined via \eqref{eq:134.3}
(independently of the choice of $L_\bullet^B$), the vertical arrows
being the localization functors. Beware that even when $A=\Simplex$
and $L_\bullet^B$ is the usual, ``standard''\pspage{559} integrator
for $\Simplex$, the upper horizontal arrow in \eqref{eq:134.7} is
\emph{not} the Kan-Dold-Puppe equivalence of categories, it has to be
followed still by the ``normalization'' operation. Thus, \emph{we
certainly should not expect in any case the functor \eqref{eq:134.5}
to be an equivalence -- however, we suspect that when $A$ is a test
category} (maybe even a weak test category would do it), \emph{then
the lower horizontal arrow in \eqref{eq:134.7}}
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.8}
\HotabOf_A \to \D_\bullet\Ab=\HotabOf \tag{8}
\end{equation}
\emph{is an equivalence of categories}. Whenever true, for a given
category $A$, this statement looks like a reasonable substitute (on
the level of the relevant derived categories) for the Kan-Dold-Puppe
theorem, known in the two cases $\Simplex$ and $\Globe$.
There are however still two important extra features in the case
$A=\Simplex$, which deserve to be understood in the case of more
general $A$. One is that a map $u:F\to G$ in \Ahatab{} is in
$W_A\supab$ (i.e., is an ``abelian weak equivalence'') if{f} it is in
$W_A$, i.e., if{f} it is a weak equivalence when forgetting the
abelian structures. In terms of a final object $e$ in $A$ (when such
object exists indeed),\footnote{it is enough that $A$ be $1$-connected
instead of having a final object} viewing the categories $A_{/F}$
(for $F$ in \Ahatab) pointed by the zero map $e\to F$, which yields
the necessary base-point $e_F$ for defining homotopy invariants
$\pi_i(F)$ for $i\ge0$, the relationship just considered between
abelian weak equivalence and weak equivalence, will follow of course
whenever we have functorial isomorphisms
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.9}
\pi_i(F) \eqdef \pi_i(A_{/F},e_F) \simeq \mathrm H_i(A,F),\tag{9}
\end{equation}
which are known to exist indeed in the case $A=\Simplex$. It should be
noted that in section~\ref{sec:92}, when starting (in a somewhat
casual way) with some reflections on ``abelianization'', we introduced
a category (denoted by $\HotabOf_A$) by localizing \Ahatab{} with
respect to the maps which are weak equivalences (when forgetting the
abelian structures), whereas it has now become clear that, in case the
latter should not coincide with the ``abelian weak equivalences''
defined in terms of linearization or homology, it is the category
\eqref{eq:134.6} definitely which is the right one. Still, the
question of defining isomorphisms \eqref{eq:134.9} when $A$ has a
final object, and whether the equality
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:134.10}
W_A\supab = \forg_A^{-1}(W_A)\tag{10}
\end{equation}
holds, where
\[\forg_A:\Ahatab\to\Ahat\]
is the ``forgetful functor'', should be settled for general $A$.
The\pspage{560} other ``extra feature'' is about the relationship of
$W_A\supab$ with the notion of homotopism. In case $A=\Simplex$, a map
in \Ahatab{} is a weak equivalence (or equivalently, an abelian weak
equivalence) if{f} it is a homotopism when forgetting the abelian
structures -- this follows from the well-known fact that
semisimplicial groups are Kan complexes. There is of course also a
notion of homotopism in the stronger abelian sense -- a particular
case of the notion of a homotopism between semisimplicial objects in
an arbitrary category (here in \Ab). The Kan-Dold-Puppe theory implies
that if $F$ and $G$ in \Simplexhatab{} have as values projective
\bZ-modules, then a map $F\to G$ in \Simplexhatab{} is a weak
equivalence if{f} it is an ``abelian'' homotopism; and likewise, two
maps $u,v: F\rightrightarrows G$ are equal in $\HotabOf_\Simplex$ if{f}
they are homotopic (in the strict, \emph{abelian} sense of the
word). The corresponding statements still make sense and are true,
when replacing \bZ{} by any ground ring $k$, working in
$\Simplex_k\adjuphat$ rather than $\Simplex_\bZ\adjuphat =
\Simplexhatab$ -- and more generally still, when working in
\[\Simplex\adjuphat_\scrM = \bHom(\Simplexop, \scrM),\]
where \scrM{} is any abelian category. Now, replacing $\Simplex$ by an
arbitrary object $A$ in \Cat, these statements still make sense, it
would seem, provided we got on \Ahat{} a suitable ``homotopy
structure'', more specifically, a suitable ``homotopy interval
structure'' (in the sense of section~\ref{sec:51}). In
section~\ref{sec:97} (p.~\ref{p:355}) we reviewed the three standard
homotopy interval structures which may be introduced on a category
\Ahat, and their relationships -- the main impression remaining was
that, in case $A$ is a \emph{contractor} (cf.\ section~\ref{sec:95}),
those three structures coincide, and may be defined also in terms of a
\emph{contractibility structure} on \Ahat{} (section~\ref{sec:51}),
the latter giving rise (via the general construction of
section~\ref{sec:79}) to the usual notion of weak equivalence $W_A$ in
\Ahat. Thus, we may hope that the feature just mentioned for
$\Simplexhat$ may be valid too for \Ahat, whenever $A$ is a
contractor. In case $A$ is only a test category, then the most
reasonable homotopy interval structure on \Ahat, I would think, which
possibly may still yield the desired ``extra feature'', is the one
defined in terms of the set $W_A$ of weak equivalences in \Ahat{} as
in section~\ref{sec:54} (namely $h_{W_A}$).
% 135
\hangsection[Proof of ``integrators are abelianizators'' (block
against \dots]{Proof of ``integrators are abelianizators''
\texorpdfstring{\textup(}{(}block against homology
receding?\texorpdfstring{\textup)}{)}.}\label{sec:135}%
This handful of questions (some of which we met with before) is mainly
a way of coming into touch again with the abelianization story, which
has been becoming somewhat remote during the previous two months. I am
not sure I am going to\pspage{561} make any attempt, now or later, to
come to an answer. The last one, anyhow, seems closely related to the
formalism of closed model structure on categories \Ahat, and the
proper place for dealing with it would seem to be rather next chapter
VII,\scrcomment{I guess AG thought this was still
Part~\ref{ch:VI}. Since there was never a second volume of PS, we
refer to \textcite{Cisinski2006} for a discussion of closed model
structures on presheaf topoi, now known as \emph{Cisinski model
structures}\dots} where such structures are going to be
studied. What I would like to do, however, here-and-now, is to
establish at last the long promised relationship ``integrators are
abelianizators'', which we have kept turning around and postponing
ever since section~\ref{sec:99}, when those integrators were finally
introduced, mainly for this purpose (of furnishing us with
``abelianizators'').
First of all, I should be more outspoken than I have been before, in
defining the ``\emph{abelianization functor}'' (or ``\emph{absolute
Whitehead functor}''):
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.1}
\bWh: \Hot\eqdef\scrW^{-1}\Cat \to \HotabOf
\eqdef\D_\bullet\Ab,\tag{1}
\end{equation}
without any use of the semisimplicial machinery which, at the
beginning of our reflections, had rather obscured the picture
(section~\ref{sec:92}). Defining such a functor amounts to defining a
functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.2}
\LH_\bullet:\Cat\to\D_\bullet\Ab,\tag{2}
\end{equation}
or ``total homology functor'', which should take weak equivalences
into isomorphisms. For an object $A$ in \Cat, we define
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.3}
\LH_\bullet(A) = \LH_\bullet(A,\bZ_A) =
\mathrm L{p_A}_!\supab(\bZ_A),\tag{3}
\end{equation}
where $\bZ_A$ is the constant abelian presheaf on $A$ with value \bZ,
and
\[p_A : A\to e\]
is the map to the final object of \Cat. We have to define the
functorial dependence on $A$. More generally, for pairs
\[(A,F), \quad\text{with $A$ in \Cat, $F$ in \Ahatab,}\]
the expression
\[\LH_\bullet(A,F)\quad\text{in $\D_\bullet\Ab$}\]
is functorial with respect to the pair $(A,F)$, where a map
\[(A,F) \to (A',F')\]
is defined to be a pair $(f,u)$, where
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.4}
f: A\to A', \quad
u: F\to f^*(F'),\tag{4}
\end{equation}
the composition of maps being the obvious one. To see that such a pair
defines a map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.5}
\LH_\bullet(f,u): \LH_\bullet(A,F) \to \LH_\bullet(A',F'),\tag{5}
\end{equation}
we\pspage{562} use
\[p_A = p_{A'} \circ f,\]
hence
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.star}
(p_A)_!\supab \simeq (p_{A'})_!\supab \circ f_!\supab,
\quad\text{and}\quad
\mathrm L(p_A)_!\supab \simeq \mathrm L(p_{A'})_!\supab
\circ \mathrm Lf_!\supab,\tag{*}
\end{equation}
taking into account that $f_!\supab$ maps projectives to
projectives. Hence, we get
\[\LH_\bullet(A,F)\eqdef \mathrm L(p_A)_!\supab(F) \simeq
\mathrm L(p_{A'})_!\supab(\mathrm Lf_!\supab(F)) \eqdef
\LH_\bullet(A',\mathrm Lf_!\supab(F)).\]
This, in order to get \eqref{eq:135.5}, we need only define a map in
$\D^-({A'}\uphat\subab)$
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.6}
\mathrm Lf_!\supab(F)\to F',\tag{6}
\end{equation}
which will be obtained as the composition
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.6prime}
\mathrm Lf_!\supab(F)\to f_!\supab(F) \to F',\tag{6'}
\end{equation}
where the first map in \eqref{eq:135.6prime} is the canonical
augmentation maps towards the $\mathrm H_0$ object, and where the
second corresponds to $u$ in \eqref{eq:135.4} by adjunction. This
defines the map \eqref{eq:135.5}, and compatibility with compositions
should be a tautology. Hence the functor \eqref{eq:135.2}. To get
\eqref{eq:135.1}, we still have to check that when
\[f:A\to A'\]
is a weak equivalence, then
\[\LH_\bullet(f): \LH_\bullet(A) \to \LH_\bullet(A')\]
is an isomorphism in $\D_\bullet\Ab$. It amounts to the same to check
that for any object $K^\bullet$ in $\D^+\Ab$, the corresponding map
between the $\RHom$'s with values in $K^\bullet$ is an isomorphism in
$\D^+\Ab$. But the latter map can be identified with the map for
\emph{cohomology}
\[\RH^\bullet(A', K_{A'}^\bullet) \to \RH^\bullet(A, K_A^\bullet),\]
with coefficients in the constant complex of presheaves defined by
$K^\bullet$ on $A'$ and on $A$, which is an isomorphism, by the very
definition of weak equivalences in \Cat{} via cohomology.
Now, the statement ``an integrator is an abelianizator'' may be
rephrased rather evidently, without any reference to a given
integrator, as merely the commutativity, up to canonical isomorphism,
of the following diagram for a given $A$ in \Cat:\pspage{563}
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.7}
\begin{tabular}{@{}c@{}}
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),column sep=large]
\Ahat \ar[r,"\varphi_A"]\ar[d,"\Wh_A"'] &
\Hot\ar[d,"{\bWh}"] \\
\Ahatab \ar[r,"{\LH_\bullet(A,{-})}"'] &
|[alias=O]| {\ooalign{$\Hotab$\cr$\Hotab\eqdef\D_\bullet\Ab$\hidewidth\cr}}
\end{tikzcd}\qquad\qquad,
\end{tabular}\tag{7}
\end{equation}
or equivalently, of the corresponding diagram where the categories
\Ahat, \Ahatab{} are replaced by the relevant localizations:
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.7prime}
\begin{tabular}{@{}c@{}}
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base)]
\HotOf_A \ar[r]\ar[d] &
\HotOf \ar[d] \\
\HotabOf_A \ar[r] &
|[alias=O]| \HotabOf
\end{tikzcd}.
\end{tabular}\tag{7'}
\end{equation}
The left vertical arrow in \eqref{eq:135.7} is of course the trivial
abelianization functor in \Ahat:
\[\Wh_A:\Ahat\to\Ahatab, \quad
X\mapsto \bZ^{(X)}=\bigl(a\mapsto \bZ^{(X(a))}\bigr).\]
Going back to the definitions, the commutativity of \eqref{eq:135.7}
up to isomorphism, means that for $X$ in \Ahat, there is a canonical
isomorphism
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.8}
\LH_\bullet(A_{/X},\bZ) \simeq\LH_\bullet(A, \bZ^{(X)}),\tag{8}
\end{equation}
functorial with respect to $X$. To define \eqref{eq:135.8}, let
\[f : A'\eqdef A_{/X} \to A\]
be the canonical functor, then we get (using \eqref{eq:135.star} of
the previous page, with the roles of $A$ and $A'$ reversed)
\[\LH_\bullet(A',\bZ_{A'}) \simeq \LH_\bullet(A, \mathrm
Lf_!\supab(\bZ_{A'})),\]
and the relation \eqref{eq:135.8} follows from the more precise
relation
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.9}
\mathrm Lf_!\supab(\bZ_{A'}) \tosim \bZ^{(X)}.\tag{9}
\end{equation}
To get \eqref{eq:135.9}, we remark that we have the tautological
relation
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.9prime}
f_!\supab(\bZ_{A'}) \simeq \bZ^{(X)},\tag{9'}
\end{equation}
hence the map \eqref{eq:135.9}. To prove it is an isomorphism amounts
to proving
\[\mathrm L_if_!\supab(\bZ_{A'}) = 0\quad\text{for $i>0$,}\]
but we have indeed
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.10}
\mathrm L_if_!\supab = 0\quad
\text{for $i>0$, i.e., $f_!\supab$ is \emph{exact},}
\tag{10}
\end{equation}
not only right exact, a rather special feature, valid for a
localization\pspage{564} functor like $f:A_{/X}\to A$, namely for a
functor which is fibering (in the sense of the theory of ``fibered
categories'') and has discrete fibers. It comes from the explicit
description of $f_!\supab$, as
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:135.11}
f_!\supab(F) = \Bigl( a\mapsto \bigoplus_{u\in X(a)} F(a)_u\Bigr),\tag{11}
\end{equation}
where, for a group object $F$ in $\Ahat_{/X}\simeq(A_{/X})\uphat$, and
$u$ in $X(a)$ (defining therefore an object of $A_{/X}$) $F(a)_u = $
fiber of $F(a)$ at $u\in X(a)$ is the corresponding abelian
group. I'll leave the proof of \eqref{eq:135.11} to the reader, it
should be more or less tautological.
Once the whole proof is written down, it looks so simple that I feel
rather stupid and can't quite understand why I have turned around it
for so long, rather than writing it down right away more than three
months ago! The reason surely is that I have been accustomed so
strongly to expressing everything via cohomology rather than homology,
that there has been something like a block against doing work
homologically, when it is homology which is involved. This block has
remained even after I took the trouble of telling myself quite
outspokenly (in section~\ref{sec:100}) that homology was just as
important and meaningful as cohomology, and more specifically still
(in section~\ref{sec:103}) that the proof I had in mind first, via
Quillen's result about $A\simeq A\op$ in \Hot{} and via cohomology,
was an ``awkward'', an ``upside-down'', one. The review on
abelianization I went into just after made things rather worse in a
sense, as there I took great pains to make the point that homology and
cohomology were just one and the same thing (so why bother about
homology!). Still, I \emph{did} develop some typically homologically
flavored formalism with the $*_k$ operation, and I hope that at the
end that block of mine is going to recede\dots
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{27.10.}\pspage{565}\par
% 136
\hangsection[Preliminary perplexities about a full-fledged ``six
\dots]{Preliminary perplexities about a full-fledged ``six operations
duality formalism'' within
\texorpdfstring{\Cat}{(Cat)}.}\label{sec:136}%
I just spent a couple of hours, after reading the notes of last night,
trying to get a better feeling of the basic homology operation in the
context of the basic localizer \Cat, namely taking the left derived
functor $\mathrm Lf_!\supab$ of the ``unusual'' direct image functor
for abelian presheaves, associated to a map
\[f: A \to B\]
in \Cat. This led me to read again the notes of section~\ref{sec:92},
when I unsuspectingly started on an ``afterthought, later gradually
turning into a systematic reflection on abelianization. With a
distance of nearly four months, what strikes me most now in these
notes is awkwardness of the approach followed at start, when yielding
to the reflex of laziness of describing abelianization of homotopy
types via the semisimplicial grindmill. The uneasiness in these notes
is obvious throughout -- I kind of knew ``au fond''\scrcomment{``au
fond'' -- at the bottom -- deep down} that dragging in
the particular test category $\Simplex$ was rather silly. In
section~\ref{sec:100} only, does it get clear that the best
description for abelianization, with the modelizer \Cat, is via the
unusual direct image $p_!\supab$ corresponding to the projection
\[p=p_A:A\to e\]
of the ``model'' $A$ in \Cat{} to the final object (formulæ
\eqref{eq:100.11} and \eqref{eq:100.12} page~\ref{p:359}), by applying
$p_!\supab$ to a ``cointegrator'' $L_\bullet^A$ for $A$, namely to a
projective resolution of $\bZ_A$ (where $A$ is written $B$ by the way,
as I had been led before to replace a given $A$ in \Cat{} by its
``dual'' or opposite $B=A\op$, bound as I was for interpreting
``integrators'' for $A$ in terms of ``cointegrators'' for $B$\dots);
and in the next section the step is finally taken (against the
``block''!) to write
\[p_!\supab(L_\bullet^B)=\mathrm Lp_!\supab(\bZ_B),\]
which inserts abelianization into the familiar formalism of (left)
derived functors of standard functors. The reasonable next thing to do
was of course what I finally did only yesterday, namely check the
commutativity of the diagram \eqref{eq:135.7} of p.~\ref{p:563},
namely compatibility of this notion of abelianization (or homology)
with Whitehead's abelianization, when working with models coming from
\Ahat, $A$ any object in \Cat. This by the way, when applied to the
case $A=\Simplex$, gives at once the equivalence of the intrinsic
definition of abelianization, with the semisimplicial one we started
with -- provided we remark that in this case, $\mathrm Lp_!\supab$
(rather, its restriction to $\Simplexhatab$) may be equally
interpreted as the Kan-Dold-Puppe\pspage{566} functor (more
accurately, the composition of the latter with the localization
functor $\Ch_\bullet\Ab\to\D_\bullet\Ab=\HotabOf$). The equivalence of
the two definitions of abelianization is mentioned on the same
p.~\ref{p:369}, somewhat as a chore I didn't really feel then to dive
into. Besides the ``block'' against homology, the picture was being
obscured, too, by the ``computational'' idea I kept in mind, of
expressing $\mathrm Lp_!\supab(F)$ for $F$ in \Ahatab{} in terms of an
``integrator'' for $A$, i.e., as $F *_\bZ L_\bullet^B$ -- whereas I
should have known best myself that for establishing formal properties
relating various derived functors, the particular approaches used for
``computing'' them more or less elegantly are wholly irrelevant\dots
One teaching I am getting out of all this, is that when expressing
abelianization, or presumably any other kind of notion or operation of
significance for homotopy types, one should be careful, for any
modelizer one chooses to work in, to dig out the description which
fits smoothly those particular models. Clearly, when working with
semisimplicial models, the description via tautological abelianization
$\Wh_\Simplex$ and using Kan-Dold-Puppe is the best. When working
within the modelizer \Cat, though, making the detour through
\Simplexhat{} is awkward and makes us just miss the relevant
facts. Once we got this, it gets clear, too, what to do when
$\Simplex$ is replaced by any other object $A$ in \Cat{} when taking
models in \Ahat{} (never minding even whether \Ahat{} is indeed a
``modelizer''): namely, apply $\Wh_A$, and take total homology!
This brings to my mind another example, very similar indeed. Some time
after I got across Thomason's nice paper, showing that \Cat{} is a
closed model category (see comments in section~\ref{sec:87}), I got
from Tim Porter another reprint of
Thomason's,\scrcomment{\textcite{Thomason1979}} where he gives the
description of ``homotopy colimits'' (or ``integration'', as I call
it) within the modelizer \Cat, in terms of the total category
associated to a fibered category (compare section~\ref{sec:69}). There
he grinds through a tedious, highly technical proof, whereas the
direct proof when describing ``integration'' as the left adjoint
functor to the tautological ``inverse image'' functor, is more or less
tautological, too. The reason for this awkwardness is again that,
rather than being content to work with the models as they are,
Thomason refers to the
Bousfield-Kan\scrcomment{\textcite{BousfieldKan1972}} description of
colimits in the semisimplicial set-up which he takes as his definition
for colimits. I suspect that \Cat{} is the one modelizer most ideally
suited for expressing the ``integration'' operation, and that the
Bousfield-Kan description is just the obvious, not-quite-as-simple one
which can be deduced\pspage{567} from the former, using the relevant
two functors between \Cat{} and \Simplexhat{} which allow to pass from
one type of models to another. (Sooner or later I should check in
Bousfield-Kan's book whether this is so or not\dots)\enspace Thomason,
however, did the opposite, and it is quite natural that he had to pay
for it by a fair amount of sweat! (Reference of the paper: Homotopy
colimits in the category of small categories, Math.\ Proc.\ Cambridge
Philos.\ Soc.\ (1979), 85, p.~91--109.)
The proof written down yesterday for compatibility of abelianization
of homotopy types with the Whitehead abelianization functor within a
category \Ahat, still goes through when replacing abelianization by
$k$-linearization, with respect to an arbitrary ground ring $k$ (not
even commutative). It wasn't really worth while, though, to introduce
a ring $k$, as the general result should follow at once from the case
$k=\bZ$, by the formula
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:136.1}
\mathrm Lp_!^k(k_A) \simeq \mathrm Lp_!^\bZ(\bZ_A) \Lotimes_\bZ
k,\tag{1}
\end{equation}
where in the left-hand side we are taking the left derived functor for
the functor
\[p_!^k : A\uphat_k \to (\AbOf_k)\]
generalizing $p_!\supab = p_!^\bZ$ (with $p: A\to e$ as above), and
where in the right-hand side we are using the ring extension functor
\[\Lotimes_\bZ : \D_\bullet\Ab\to\D_\bullet(\AbOf_k)\]
for the relevant derived categories. This reminds me of the need of
developing a more or less exhaustive formulaire around the basic
operations
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:136.2}
\mathrm Lf_!, \quad f^*, \quad \mathrm Rf_*,\tag{2}
\end{equation}
including the familiar one for the two latter, valid more generally
for maps between ringed topoi, and including also a ``\emph{projection
formula}'' generalizing \eqref{eq:136.1}. Such a formula will be no
surprise, surely, to a reader familiar with a duality context (such as
étale cohomology, or ``coherent'' cohomology of noetherian schemes,
say), where a formalism of the ``four variances'' $f_!$, $f^*$, $f_*$,
$f^!$ and the ``two internal operations'' $\Lotimes$ and $\RbHom$ can
be developed -- it would seem that the formal properties of the triple
\eqref{eq:136.2}, together with the two internal operations just
referred to, are very close (for the least) to those of the slightly
richer one in duality set-ups, including equally an ``unusual inverse
image'' $f^!$, right adjoint to $\mathrm Rf_*$ (denoted sometimes
simply by $f_*$). This similarity\pspage{568} is a matter of course,
as far as the two last among the functors \eqref{eq:136.2}, together
with the two internal operations, are concerned, as in both contexts
(homology and cohomology formalism within \Cat{} on the one hand, and
the ``sweeping duality formalism'' on the other) the formulaire
concerning these four operations
\[f^*, \quad \mathrm Rf_*, \quad {\Lotimes}, \quad \RbHom\]
is no more, no less than just the relevant formulaire in the context
of arbitrary (commutatively) ringed topoi, and maps between such. The
common notation $f_!$ (occurring in $\mathrm Lf_!$ in the \Cat{}
context, in $\mathrm Rf_!$ in the ``duality'' context) is a very
suggestive one, for the least, and I am rather confident that most
reflexes (concerning formal behavior of $f_!$ with respect to the
other operations) coming from one context, should be OK too in the
other. Whether this is just a mere formal analogy, or whether there is
a deeper relationship between the two kinds of contexts, I am at a
loss at present to say. It doesn't seem at all unlikely to me that
among arbitrary maps in \Cat, one can single out some, by some kind of
``finite type'' condition, for which a functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:136.star}
f^! : \D^+(B\uphat_k) \to \D^+(A\uphat_k)\tag{*}
\end{equation}
can be defined (where $f:A\to B$), right adjoint to the familiar
$\mathrm Rf_*$ functor, so that \eqref{eq:136.2} can be completed to a
sequence of \emph{four} functors
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:136.3}
\mathrm Lf_!, \quad f^*, \quad \mathrm Rf_*, \quad f^!,\tag{3}
\end{equation}
forming a sequence of mutually adjoint functors between derived
categories, in the usual sense (the functor immediately to the right
of another being its right adjoint). I faintly remember that Verdier
worked out such a formalism within the context of discrete or
profinite groups, or both, in a Bourbaki talk he gave, this being
inspired by the similar work he did within the context of usual
topological spaces. In the latter, the finiteness condition required
for a map
\[f:X\to Y\]
of topological spaces to give rise to a functor $f^!$ (between, say,
the derived categories of the categories of abelian sheaves on $Y$ and
$X$) is mainly that $X$ should be locally embeddable in a product
$Y\times \bR^d$ -- a rather natural condition indeed! As we are using
\Cat{} as a kind of algebraic paradigm for the category of topological
spaces, this last example for ``sweeping duality'' makes it rather
plausible that something of the same kind should exist indeed in
\Cat{} -- and likewise for the context of groups (which we may view as
just particular cases of\pspage{569} models in \Cat).
I am sorry I was a bit confused, when describing $f^!$ as a right
adjoint to $\mathrm Rf_*$ -- I was thinking of the analogy with a map
of schemes, or spaces, which is not only ``of finite type'' in a
suitable sense, but moreover \emph{proper} -- in which case, in those
duality contexts, $\mathrm Rf_*$ is canonically isomorphic with the
functor denoted by $f_!$ or $\mathrm Rf_!$. Otherwise, the
(``non-trivial'') ``duality theorem'' will assert, rather, that the
pair
\[\mathrm Rf_!,\quad f^!\]
is a pair of adjoint functors, just as is the pair
\[f^*,\quad \mathrm Rf_*\quad\text{(or simply $f_*$).}\]
But even when $f$ is assumed to be proper, the sequence
\eqref{eq:136.3} isn't a sequence of adjoint functors in the standard
duality contexts, namely $\mathrm Rf_!$ is by no means left adjoint to
$f^*$, i.e., $f^*$ isn't isomorphic to $f^!$ (except in extremely
special cases, practically I would think only étale maps are OK, which
in the context of \Cat{} would correspond to maps in \Cat{} isomorphic
to a map $A_{/X}\to A$ for $X$ in \Ahat, namely maps which are
fibering with discrete fibers). This \emph{does} make an important
discrepancy indeed, between the two kinds of contexts -- and increases
my perplexity, as to whether or not one should expect a ``four
variance duality formalism'' to make sense in \Cat. If so, presumably
the $f_!$ or $\mathrm Rf_!$ it will involve (perhaps via a suitable
notion of ``proper'' maps in \Cat, as already referred to earlier
(section~\ref{sec:70})) will be different after all from the $\mathrm
Lf_!$ we have been working with lately, embodying homology
properties. But so does $\mathrm Rf_!$ too, in a rather strong sense,
via the ``duality theorem''!
In the various duality contexts, a basic part is played by the three
particular classes of maps: proper maps, smooth maps, and immersions,
and factorizations of maps into an immersion followed by either a
proper, or a smooth map. In the context of Cat, there is a very
natural way indeed to define the three classes of maps, as we'll see
in the next chapter, presumably -- so natural indeed, that it is hard
to believe that there may be any other reasonable choice! One very
striking feature (already mentioned in section~\ref{sec:70}) is that
the two first notions are ``dual'' to each other in the rather
tautological sense, namely that a map $f:A\to B$ in \Cat{} is proper
if{f} the corresponding map $f\op:A\op\to B\op$ is smooth (whereas the
notion of an immersion is\pspage{570} autodual). How does this fit
with the expectation of developing a ``four variance'' duality
formalism within \Cat? It rather heightens perplexity at first sight!
Proper maps include cofibrations (in the sense of category theory, not
in Kan-Quillen's sense!); dually, smooth maps include
fibrations. Consequently, maps which are moth smooth and proper
include bifibrations, and hence are not too uncommon. Now, how strong
a restriction is it for a map $f:A\to B$ in \Cat{} to factor into
\[f=p\circ i,\]
where $i$ is an immersion $A\to A'$ (namely, a functor identifying $A$
to a full subcategory of $A'$, whose essential image includes, with
any two objects $x,y$, any other $z$ which is ``in between'': $x\to
z\to y$), and $p$ is both proper and smooth (a bifibration, say)?
I start feeling like a battle horse scenting gunpowder again -- still,
I don't think I'll run into it. Surely, there is something to be
cleared up, and perhaps once again a beautiful duality formalism with
the six operations and all will emerge out of darkness -- but this
time I will not do the pulling. Maybe someone else will -- if he isn't
discouraged beforehand, because the big-shots all seem kind of blasé
with ``big duality'', derived categories and all that. As for my
present understanding, I feel that the question isn't really about
homotopy models, or about foundations of homotopy and cohomology
formalism -- at any rate, that I definitely don't need this kind of
stuff, for the program I have been out for. I shouldn't refrain, of
course, to pause on the way every now and then and have a look at the
landscape, however remote or misty -- but I am not going to forget I
am bound for a journey, and that the journey should not be an unending
one\dots
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\alsoondate{27.10.}\par
% 137
\hangsection[Looking for the relevant notions of properness and
\dots]{Looking for the relevant notions of properness and smoothness
for maps in \texorpdfstring{\Cat}{(Cat)}. Case of ordered sets as a
paradigm for cohomology theory of conically stratified
spaces.}\label{sec:137}%
It occurred to me that I have been a little rash yesterday, when
asserting that the notions of ``smoothness'' and ``properness'' for
maps in \Cat{} which I hit upon last Spring is the only ``reasonable''
one. Initially, I referred to these notions by the names
``cohomologically smooth'', ``cohomologically proper'', as a measure
of caution -- they were defined by properties of commutation of base
change to formation of the Leray sheaves $\mathrm R^if_*$ (i.e.,
essentially, to ``cointegration''), which were familiar to me for
smooth resp.\ proper maps in the context of schemes, or ordinary
topological spaces. These\pspage{571} cohomological counterparts of
smoothness and properness fit very neatly into the homology and
cohomology formalism, and I played around enough with them, last
Spring as well as more than twenty years ago when developing étale
cohomology of schemes, for there being no doubt left in my mind that
these notions are relevant indeed. However, I was rather rash
yesterday, while forgetting that these cohomological versions of
smoothness and properness are considerably weaker than the usual
notions. Thus, in the context of schemes over a ground field, the
product of any two schemes is cohomologically smooth over its factors
-- or equivalently, any scheme over a field $k$ is cohomologically
smooth over $k$! Similarly, in the context of \Cat, any object in
\Cat, namely any small category, is both cohomologically smooth and
proper over the final object $e$ (as it is trivially ``bifibered''
over $e$). On the other hand, it isn't reasonable, of course, to
expect any kind of Poincaré-like duality to hold for the cohomology
(with twisted coefficients, say) of an arbitrary object $A$ in
\Cat. To be more specific, it is easy to see that in many cases, the
functor
\[\mathrm Rf_* : \D^+(\Ahatab)\to\D^+\Ab\]
does not admit a right adjoint (which we would call $f^!$). For
instance, when $A$ is discrete, then $f^!$ exists (and may then be
identified with $f^*$) if{f} $A$ is moreover \emph{finite} -- a rather
natural condition indeed, when we keep in mind the topological
significance of the usual notion of properness! This immediately
brings to mind some further properties besides base change properties,
which go with the intuitions around properness -- for instance, we
would expect for proper $f$, the functors $f_*$ and $\mathrm Rf_*$ to
commute to filtering direct limits, and the same expectation goes with
the assumption that $\mathrm Rf_*$ should admit a right adjoint. This
exactness property is not satisfied, of course, when $A$ is discrete
infinite. We now may think (still in case of target category equal to
$e$) to impose the drastic condition that the category $A$ is
finite. Such restriction however looks in some respects too weak, in
others too strong. Thus, it will include categories defined by finite
groups, which goes against the rather natural expectation that
properness + smoothness, or any kind of Poincaré duality, should go
with \emph{finite cohomological dimension}. On the other hand, there
are beautiful infinite groups (such as the fundamental group of a
compact surface, or of any other compact variety that is a $K(\pi,1)$
space\dots) which satisfy Poincaré duality.
These\pspage{572} reflections make it quite clear that the notions of
properness and of smoothness for maps in \Cat, relevant for a duality
formalism, have still to be worked out. Two basic requirements to be
kept in mind are the following: \namedlabel{rem:137.1}{1)}\enspace for
a proper map $f: A\to B$, and any ring of coefficients $k$, the
functor
\[\mathrm Rf_* : \D^+(A\uphat_k)\to\D^+(B\uphat_k)\]
should admit a right adjoint $f^!$, and
\namedlabel{rem:137.2}{2)}\enspace for a smooth map $f$ factored as
$f=g\circ i$, with $g$ proper and $i$ an ``open immersion'', the
composition $f^!\eqdef i^*\circ g^!$ should be expressible as
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.5}
f^!: K^\bullet \mapsto f^*(K)\Lotimes_k T_f(k)[d_f],\tag{5}
\end{equation}
where $T_f(k)$ is a presheaf of $k$-modules on $A$ locally isomorphic
to the constant presheaf $k_A$ ($T_f(k)$ may be called the
\emph{orientation sheaf} for $f$, with coefficients in $k$), and $d_f$
is a natural integer (which may be called the \emph{relative
dimension} of $A$ over $B$, or of $f$). (For simplicity, I assume in
\ref{rem:137.2} that $A$ is connected, otherwise $d_f$ should be
viewed as a function on the set of connected components of
$A$.)\enspace This again should give the correct relationship, for $f$
as above, between the (for the time being hypothetical) $\mathrm Rf_!$
($\eqdef \mathrm Rg_*\circ\mathrm Lf_!$) and our anodyne $\mathrm
Lf_!$, for an argument $L_\bullet$ in $\D^\bullet(A\uphat_k)$ say:
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.6}
\mathrm Rf_!(L_\bullet) \simeq \mathrm Lf_!(L_\bullet \otimes
T_f^{-1})[-d_f],\tag{6}
\end{equation}
where the left-hand side is just $\mathrm Rf_*(L_\bullet)$, if we
assume moreover $f$ to be proper.
This precise relationship between the two possible versions of an
$f_!$ operation between derived categories, namely $\mathrm Lf_!$
embodying homology, defined for any map $f$ in \Cat, and
$\mathrm Rf_!$ embodying ``cohomology with proper supports'', defined
for a map that may be factored as $g\circ i$ with $g$ ``proper'' and
$i$ an (open, if we like) immersion, relation valid if $f$ is moreover
assumed to be ``smooth'', greatly relaxes yesterday's perplexity,
coming from a partial confusion in my mind between the operations
$\mathrm Rf_!$ and $\mathrm Lf_!$. (Beware the notation $\mathrm Rf_!$
is an abuse, as it doesn't mean at all anything like the right derived
functor of the functor $f_!$!)\enspace At the same time, I feel a lot
less dubious now about the existence of a ``six operations'' duality
formalism in the \Cat{} context -- I am pretty much convinced, now,
that such a formalism exists indeed. The main specific work ahead is
to get hold of the relevant notions of proper and smooth maps. The
demands we have on\pspage{573} these, besides the relevant base change
properties, are so precise, one feels, that they may almost be taken
as a definition! Maybe even the ``almost'' could be dropped -- namely
that a comprehensive axiomatic set-up for the duality formalism could
be worked out, in a way applicable to the known instances as well as
to the presently still unknown one of \Cat, by going a little further
still than Deligne's exposition in
SGA~5\scrcomment{\textcite[Dualité]{SGA4andhalf}} (where the notions
of ``smooth'' and ``proper'' maps were supposed to be given
beforehand, satisfying suitable properties). Before diving into such
axiomatization game, one should get a better feeling, though, through
a fair number of examples (not all with $e$ as the target category
moreover), of how the proper, the smooth and the proper-and-smooth
maps in \Cat{} actually look like. Here, presumably, Verdier's work in
the context of discrete infinite groups should give useful clues.
Other important clues should come from the opposite side so to say --
namely ordered sets. Such a set $I$, besides defining in the usual way
a small category and hence a topos, may equally be viewed as a
topological space, more accurately, the topos it defines may be viewed
as being associated to a topological space, admitting $I$ as its
underlying set (cf.\ section~\ref{sec:22}, p.~\ref{p:18}). This
topological space is noetherian if{f} the ordered set $I$ is -- for
instance if $I$ is finite. In such a case, an old algebraic geometer
like me will feel in known territory, which maybe is a delusion,
however -- at any rate, I doubt the duality formalism for topological
spaces (using factorizations of maps $X\to Y$ via embeddings in spaces
$Y\times\bR^d$) makes much sense for such non-separated
spaces. However, as we saw in section~\ref{sec:22}, when $I$ satisfies
some mild ``local finiteness'' requirement (for instance when $I$ is
finite), we may associate to it a \emph{geometrical realization} $\abs
I$, which is a locally compact space (a compact one indeed if $I$ is
finite) endowed with a ``conical subdivision'' (index by the opposite
ordered set $I\op$), hence canonically triangulated via the
``barycentric subdivision''. The homotopy type of this space is
canonically isomorphic to the homotopy type of $I$, viewed as a
``model'' in \Cat. What is more important here, is that a (pre)sheaf
of sets (say) on the category $I$ may be interpreted as being
essentially the same as a sheaf of sets on the geometric realization
$\abs I$ \emph{which is locally constant} (\emph{and hence constant})
\emph{on each of the \emph{``open''} strata or ``cones'' of $I$}. This
description then carries over to sheaves of $k$-modules. The ``clue''
I had in mind is that \emph{within the context of locally finite
ordered sets, the looked-for ``six operations duality formalism''
should be no more, no less than the accurate reflection of the same
formalism within the context\pspage{574} of \textup(locally
compact\textup) topological spaces}, as worked out by Verdier in one
of his Bourbaki talks -- it being understood that when applying the
latter formalism to spaces endowed with conical stratifications, maps
between these which are compatible with the stratifications (in a
suitable sense which should still be pinned down), and to sheaves of
modules which are compatible with the stratifications in the sense
above, these will give rise (via the ``six operations'') to sheaves
satisfying the same compatibility. (NB\enspace when speaking of
``sheaves'', I really mean complexes of sheaves $K^\bullet$, and the
compatibility condition should be understood as a condition for the
ordinary sheaves of modules $\mathrm H^i(K^\bullet)$.)\enspace This
remark should allow to work out quite explicitly, in purely algebraic
(or ``combinatorial'') terms, the ``six operations'' in the context of
locally finite ordered sets, at any rate.
This interpretation suggests that an ordered set $I$ should be viewed
as a ``proper'' object of \Cat{} if{f} $I$ is finite. In the same
vein, whenever $I$ is ``locally proper'', namely locally finite, and
moreover its topological realization $\abs I$ is a ``smooth''
topological space in the usual sense, namely is a topological
\emph{variety} (for which it is enough that for every $x$ in $I$, the
topological realization
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.7}
\abs{I_{>x}}\tag{7}
\end{equation}
of the set of elements $y$ such that $y>x$ should be a sphere), we
would consider $I$ as a ``smooth'' object in \Cat. If $A$ is any
object in \Cat{} and $I$ is an ordered set which is finite resp.\
``smooth'' in the sense above, we will surely expect $A\times I\to A$
to be ``proper'' resp.\ ``smooth'' for the duality formalism we wish
to develop in \Cat.
It should be kept in mind that for the algebraic interpretation above
to hold, for sheaves on a conically stratified space $\abs I$ in terms
of an ordered set $I$, we had to take on the indexing set $I$ for the
strata the order relation \emph{opposite} to the inclusion relation
between (closed) strata -- otherwise, the correct interpretation of
sheaves constant on the open strata is via \emph{covariant} functors
$I\to\Sets$, i.e., \emph{presheaves on $I\op$} (not $I$). At any rate,
as there is a canonical homeomorphism
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.8}
\abs I\simeq\abs{I\op}\tag{8}
\end{equation}
respecting the canonical barycentric subdivisions of both sides,
notions for $I$ (such as properness, or smoothness) which are
expressed as intrinsic properties of the corresponding topological
space $\abs I$ (independently of its subdivision) are autodual -- they
hold for $I$ if{f} they do for $I\op$.\pspage{575} This is in sharp
contrast with the more naive notions of ``cohomological'' properness
and smoothness via base change operations, which are interchanged by
duality (which was part of yesterday's perplexities, now straightening
out\dots).
I feel I should be a little more outspoken about the relevant notion
of ``proper maps'' between ordered sets, which should be the algebraic
expression of the geometric notion alluded to above, of a map between
conically stratified spaces being ``compatible with the conical
stratifications''. In order for the corresponding direct image functor
for sheaves to take sheaves compatible with the stratification above
to sheaves of same type below, we'll have to insist that the image by
$f$ of a strata above should be a whole strata below. Now, it is clear
that any map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.9}
f:I\to J\tag{9}
\end{equation}
between ordered sets takes flags into flags, and hence induces a map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:137.10}
\abs f:\abs I \to \abs J\tag{10}
\end{equation}