-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 13
/
Copy pathps4.tex
5329 lines (5097 loc) · 270 KB
/
ps4.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
%% Anti-Copyright 2015 - the scrivener
\chapter{Asphericity structures and canonical modelizers}
\label{ch:IV}
\presectionfill\alsoondate{11.4.}\pspage{188}\par
% 67
\hangsection[Setting out for the asphericity game again: variance of
\dots]{Setting out for the asphericity game again: variance of the
category \texorpdfstring{\HotA}{(Hot-A)}, for arbitrary small
category $A$ and aspheric functors.}\label{sec:67}%
A little more pondering and scribbling finally seems to show that the
real key for an understanding of modelizers isn't really the notion of
contractibility, but rather the notion of aspheric objects (besides,
of course, the notion of weak equivalence). At the same time it
appears that the notion of an \emph{aspheric map} in \Cat, more
specifically of a \scrW-aspheric ``map'' (i.e., a functor between
small categories) is a lot more important than being just a highly
expedient technical convenience, as it has been so far -- it is indeed
one of the basic notions of the theory of modelizers we got into. As a
matter of fact, I should have known this for a number of weeks
already, ever since I did some scribbling about the plausible notion
of ``morphism'' between test-categories (as well as their weak and
strong variants), and readily convinced myself that the natural
``morphisms'' here were nothing else but the aspheric functors between
those categories. I kind of forgot about this, as it didn't seem too
urgent to start moving around the category I was working with. If I
had been a little more systematic in grinding through the usual
functorialities, as soon as a significant notion (such as the various
test notions) appears, I presumably would have hit upon the crucial
point about modelizers and so-called ``asphericity structures'' a lot
sooner, without going through the long-winded detour of homotopy
structures, and the still extremely special types of test functors
suggested by the contractibility assumptions. However, I believe that
most of the work I went through, although irrelevant for the
``asphericity story'' itself, will still be useful, especially when it
comes to pinpointing the so-called ``canonical'' modelizers, whose
modelizing structure is intrinsically determined by the category
structure.
First thing now which we've to do is to have a closer look at the
meaning of asphericity for a functor between small categories. There
is no reason whatever to put any restrictions on these categories
besides smallness (namely the cardinals of the sets of objects and
arrows being in the ``universe'' we are implicitly working in, or even
more stringently still, $A$ and $B$ to be in \Cat{} namely to be
objects of that universe). Thus, we will not assume $A$ and $B$ to be
test categories or the like. We will be led to consider, for
\emph{any} small category $A$, the localization of \Ahat{} with
respect to \scrW-equivalences, which I'll denote by \HotAW{} or simply
\HotA:
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:67.1}
\HotAW=\HotA=\scrW^{-1}\Ahat.\tag{1}
\end{equation}
These\pspage{189} categories, I suspect, are quite interesting in
themselves, and they merit to be understood. Thus, one of Quillen's
results asserts that (at least for $\scrW=W_\Cat=$ ordinary weak
equivalences, but presumably his arguments will carry over to an
arbitrary \scrW) in case $A$ is a product category $\Simplex\times A_0$,
where $A_0$ is any small category and $\Simplex$ the category of
standard, ordered simplices, then \Ahat{} is a closed model category
admitting as weak equivalences the set \scrWA\footnote{\alsoondate{3.5.}
This, I quickly became aware, is a misrepresentation of Quillen's
result -- that ``weak equivalences'' he introduced are a lot
stronger than \scrWA. I'll have to come back upon this soon
enough!}; and hence \HotA, the corresponding ``homotopy category'',
admits familiar homotopy constructions, including the two types of
Dold-Puppe exact sequences, tied up with loop- and suspension
functors. It is very hard to believe that this should be a special
feature of the category $\Simplex$ as the multiplying factor -- surely
any test category or strict test category instead should do as
well. As we'll check below, the product of a local test category with
any category $A_0$ is again a local test category, hence a
test-category if both factors are (\scrW-)aspheric. Thus suggests that
maybe for any local test category $A$, the corresponding \Ahat{} is a
closed model category -- but it isn't even clear yet if the same
doesn't hold for \emph{any} small category $A$ whatever! It's surely
something worth looking at.
As we'll see presently, it is a tautology more or less that a functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:67.1again}
i:A\to B,\tag{1}
\end{equation}
giving rise to a functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:67.2}
i^*:\Bhat\to\Ahat\tag{2}
\end{equation}
(commuting to all types of direct and inverse limits), induces a
functor on the localizations
\[\overline{i^*}:\HotB\to\HotA,\]
provided $i$ is \scrW-aspheric. Thus,
\[A\mapsto\HotA\]
can be viewed as a functor with respect to $A$, provided we take as
``morphisms'' between ``objects'' $A$ the \emph{aspheric} functors
only -- i.e., it is a functor on the subcategory
$\Cat_{\textup{\scrW-asph}}$ of \Cat, having the same objects as \Cat,
but with maps restricted to be \scrW-aspheric ones.
We'll denote by
\[\HotOf(\scrW) = \scrW^{-1}\Cat\]
the homotopy category defined in terms of the basic localizer
\scrW. For any small category $A$, we get a commutative
diagram\pspage{190}
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:67.3}
\begin{tabular}{@{}c@{}}
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base)]
\Ahat\ar[r,"i_A"]\ar[d,swap,"\gamma_A"] &
\Cat\ar[d,"\text{$\gamma_\scrW$ or $\gamma$}"] \\
\HotA \ar[r,"\overline{i_A}"] &
|[alias=O]| (\HotOf(\scrW))
\end{tikzcd},
\end{tabular}
\tag{3}
\end{equation}
we denote by
\[\varphi_A=\gamma i_A = \overline{i_A}\gamma_A :
\Ahat\to(\HotOf(\scrW))\]
the corresponding composition.
Coming back to the case of a functor $i$ and corresponding $i^*$
(\eqref{eq:67.1again} and \eqref{eq:67.2}), the functors $i^*$, $i_A$,
$i_B$ do not give rise to a commutative triangle, but to a triangle
\emph{with commutation morphism} $\lambda_i$:
\[\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),column sep=small]
\Bhat\ar[rr,"i^*"]\ar[dr,swap,"i_B",""{name=iB,right}] & &
\Ahat\ar[dl,"i_A",""{name=iA,left}] \\
& |[alias=O]| \Cat \arrow[bend right=10, from=iA, to=iB, swap, "\lambda_i"] &
\end{tikzcd},\]
i.e., for any $F$ in \Bhat, we get a map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:67.4}
\lambda_i(F): i_Ai^*(F)=A_{/i^*(F)} \to i_B(F)=B_{/F} ,\tag{4}
\end{equation}
the first hand side of \eqref{eq:67.4}, also written simply $A_{/F}$
when there is no ambiguity for $i$, can be interpreted as the category
of pairs
\[(a,p), \quad a\in\Ob A,\quad p:i(a)\to F,\]
where $p$ is a map in \Bhat, $B$ identified as usual to a full
subcategory of \Bhat{} (hence $i(a)$ identified with an object of
\Bhat). The map $\lambda_i(F)$ for fixed $F$ is of course the functor
\[ (a,p) \mapsto (i(a),p).\]
The topological significance of course is clear: interpreting $i$ as
defining a ``map'' or morphisms of the corresponding topoi \Ahat{} and
\Bhat, having $i^*$ as inverse image functor, an object $F$ of \Bhat{}
gives rise to an \emph{induced topos} $\Bhat_{/F} \tosimeq
(B_{/F})\uphat$, and the restriction of the ``topos above'' \Ahat{} to
the induced $\Bhat_{/F}$, or equivalently the result of base change
$\Bhat_{/F}\to\Bhat$, gives rise to the induced morphism of topoi
$\Ahat_{/i^*(F)}\to\Bhat_{/F}$, represented precisely by the map
$\lambda_i(F)$ in \Cat.
The condition of \scrW-asphericity on $i$ may be expressed in manifold
ways, as properties of either one of the three aspects
\[\lambda_i, \quad i^*, \quad i_Ai^*\]
of the situation created by $i$, with respect to the localizing sets
\scrW, \scrWA, $\scrW_B$, or to the notion of aspheric object. As
\scrWA{} is defined in terms of \scrW{} as just the inverse image of
the latter by $i_A$, and the same for aspheric objects, it turns out
that each of the conditions we\pspage{191} are led to express on
$i^*$, can be formulated equivalently in terms of the composition
$i_Ai^*$. I'll restrict to formulate these in terms of $i^*$ only,
which will be the form most adapted to the use we are going to make
later of the notion of a \scrW-aspheric map, when introducing the
so-called ``asphericity structures'' and corresponding ``testing
functors''.
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{27.5.}\par
% 68
\hangsection{Digression on a ``new continent''.}\label{sec:68}%
It has been over six weeks now that I didn't write down any notes. The
reason for this is that I felt the story of asphericity structures and
canonical modelizers was going to come now without any problem, almost
as a matter of routine to write it down with some care -- therefore, I
started doing some scratchwork on a few questions which had been
around but kept in the background since the beginning, and which were
a lot less clear in my mind. Some reflection was needed anyhow, before
it would make much sense to start writing down anything on
these. Finally, it took longer than expected, as usual -- partly
because (as usual too!), a few surprises would turn up on my
way. Also, I finally allowed myself to become distracted by some
reflection on the ``Lego-Teichmüller construction game'', and pretty
much so during last week. The occasion was a series of informal talks
Y.\scrcomment{Y.\ = Yves Ladegaillerie} has been giving in Molino's seminar,
on Thurston's hyperbolic geometry game and his compactification of
Teichm\"uller space. Y.\ was getting interested again in mathematics
after a five year's interruption. He must have heard about my seminar
last year on ``anabelian algebraic geometry'' and the ``Teichmüller
tower'', and suggested I might drop in to get an idea about Thurston's
work. This work indeed appears as closely related in various respects
to my sporadic reflections of the last two years, just with a
diametrically opposed emphasis -- mine being on the algebro-geometric
and arithmetic aspects of ``moduli'' of algebraic curves, his on
hyperbolic riemannian geometry and the simply connected transcendental
Teichmüller spaces (rather than the algebraic modular
varieties). The main intersection appears to be interest in surface
surgery and the relation of this to the Teichmüller modular group. I
took the occasion to try and recollect about the Lego-Teichmüller
game, which I had thought of last year as a plausible, very concrete
way for modelizing and visualizing the whole tower of Teichmüller
groupoids $T_{g,\nu}$ and the main operations among these, especially
the ``cutting'' and ``gluing'' operations. The very informal talk I
gave was mainly intended for Y.\ as a matter of fact, and
it\pspage{192} was an agreeable surprise to notice that the message
this time was getting through. For the fiver or six years since my
attention became attracted by the fascinating melting-pot of key
structures in geometry, topology, arithmetic, discrete and algebraic
groups, intertwining tightly in a kind of very basic
Galois-Teichmüller theory, Y.\ has been the very first person I met
so far to have a feeling for (a not yet dulled instinct I might say,
for sensing) the extraordinary riches opening up here for
investigation. The series of talks I had given in a tentative seminar
last year had turned short, by lack of any active interest and
participation of anyone among the handful of mere listeners. And the
two or three occasions I had the years before to tell about the matter
of two-dimensional maps (``cartes'') and their amazing
algebro-arithmetic implications, to a few highbrow colleagues with
incomparably wider background and know-how than anyone around here, I
met with polite interest, or polite indifference which is the same. As
there was nobody around anyhow to take any interest the these juicy
greenlands, nobody would care to see, because there was no text-book
nor any official seminar notes to prove they existed, after a few
years I finally set off myself for a preliminary voyage.
I thought it was going to take me a week or two to tour it and kind of
recense\scrcomment{``recense'' could be translated as ``survey''}
resources. It took me five months instead of intensive work, and two
impressive heaps of notes (baptized ``La Longue Marche à travers la
théorie de Galois''), to get a first, approximative grasp of some of
the main structures and relationships involved. The main emphasis was
(still is) on an understanding of the action of profinite
Galois-groups (foremost among which \GalQQ{} and the subgroups of
finite index) on non-commutative profinite fundamental groups, and
primarily on fundamental groups of algebraic curves -- increasingly
too on those of modular varieties (more accurately, modular
\emph{multiplicities}) for such curves -- the profinite completions of
the Teichmüller group. The voyage was the most rewarding and exciting
I had in mathematics so far -- and still it became very clear that it
was just like a first glimpse upon a wholly new landscape -- one
landscape surely among countless others of a continent unknown, eager
to be discovered.
This was in the first half of the year 1981 -- just two years ago, it
turns out, but it look almost infinitely remote, because such a lot of
things took place since. Looking back, it turns out there have been
since roughly four main alternating periods of reflection, one period
of reflection on personal matters alternating with one on
mathematics. The next mathematical reflection started with a long
digression on tame topology and the ``déployment''
(``unfolding'')\pspage{193} of stratified structures, as a leading
thread towards a heuristic understanding of the natural stratification
of the Mumford-Deligne compactifications of modular multiplicities
$M_{g,\nu}$ (for curves of genus $g$ endowed with $\nu$ points). This
then led to the ``anabelian seminar'' which turned short, last
Spring. Then a month or two sicknees, intensive meditation for three
or four months, a few more months for settling some important personal
matter; and now, since February, another mathematical reflection
started.
I am unable to tell the meaning of this alternation of periods of
meditation on personal matters and periods of mathematical reflection,
which has been going through my life for the last seven years, more
and more, very much like the unceasing up and down of waves, or like a
steady breathing going through my life, without any attempt any longer
of controlling it one way or the other. One common moving force surely
is the inborn curiosity -- a thirst for getting acquainted with the
juicy things of the inexhaustible world, whether they be the breathing
body of the beloved, or the evasive substance of one's own life, or
the much less evasive substance of mathematical structure and their
delicate interplay. This thirst in itself is of a nature quite
different of the ego's -- it is the thirst of life to know about
itself, a primal creative force which, one suspects, has been around
forever, long before a human ego -- a bundle mainly of fears, of
inhibitions and self-deceptions -- came into being. Still, I am aware
that the ego is strongly involved in the particular way in which the
creative force expresses itself, in my own life or anyone else's (when
this force is allowed to come into play at all\ldots). The motivations
behind any strong energy investment, and more particularly so when it
is an activity attached with any kind of social status or prestige,
are a lot more complex and ego-driven than one generally cares to
admit. True, ambition by itself is powerless for discovering or
understanding or perceiving anything substantial whatever, neither a
mathematical relationship nor the perfume of a flower. In moments of
work and of discovery, in any creative moments in life, as a matter of
fact, ambition is absent; the Artisan is a keen interest, which is
just one of the manifold aspect of love. What however pushes us so
relentlessly to work again, and so often causes our life and passion
gradually to dry off and become insensitive, even to the kindred
passion of a follow-being, or to the unsuspected beauties and
mysteries of the very field we are supposed to be plowing -- this
force is neither love nor keen interest for the things and beings in
this world. It is interesting enough though, and surely deserves a
close look!
I\pspage{194} thought I was starting a retrospective of six weeks of
scratchwork on homotopical algebra -- and it turns out to be a (very)
short retrospective rather of the up-and-down movement of my
mathematical interests and investments during the last
years. Doubtless, the very strongest attraction, the greatest
fascination goes with the ``new world'' of anabelian algebraic
geometry. It may seem strange that instead, I am indulging in this
lengthy digression on homotopical algebra, which is almost wholly
irrelevant I feel for the Galois-Teichmüller story. The reason is
surely an inner reluctance, an unreadiness to embark upon a long-term
voyage, well knowing that it is so enticing that I may well be caught
in this game for a number of years -- not doing anything else day and
night than making love with mathematics, and maybe sleeping and eating
now and then. I have gone through this a number of times, and at times
I thought I was through. Finally, I came to admit and to accept, two
years ago, I was not through yet -- this was during the months of
meditation after the ``long march through Galois theory'' -- which had
been, too, a wholly unexpected fit of mathematical passion, not to say
frenzy. And during the last weeks, just reflecting a little here and
there upon the Teichmüller-Lego game and its arithmetical
implications, I let myself be caught again by this fascination -- it
is becoming kind of clear now that I am going to finish writing up
those notes on algebra, almost like some homework that has got to be
done (anyhow I like to finish when I started something) -- and as soon
as I'm through with the notes, back to geometry in the long last!
Also, the idea is in the air for the last few months -- since I
decided to publish these informal notes on stacks or whatever it'll
turn out to be -- that I may well go on the same way, writing up and
publishing informal notes on other topics, including tame topology and
anabelian algebraic geometry. In contrast to the present notes, I got
heaps of scratchwork done on these in the years before -- in this
respect time is even riper for me to ramble ``publicly'' than on
stacks and homotopy theory!
From Y.\ who looked through a lot of literature on the subject, it
strikes me (agreeably of course) that nobody yet hit upon ``the''
natural presentation of the Teichmüller groupoids, which kind of
imposes itself quite forcibly in the set-up I let myself be guided
by. Technically speaking (and this will rejoice Ronnie Brown I'm
sure!), I suspect one main reason why this is so, is that people are
accustomed to working with fundamental groups and generators and
relations for these and stick to it, even in contexts when this is
wholly inadequate, namely when you get a clear\pspage{195} description
by generators and relations only when working simultaneously with a
whole bunch of base-points chosen with case -- or equivalently,
working in the algebraic context of \emph{groupoids}, rather than
groups. Choosing paths for connecting the base-points natural to the
situation to just one among them, and reducing the groupoid to a
single group, will then hopelessly destroy the structure and inner
symmetries of the situation, and result in a mess of generators and
relations no-one dares to write down, because everyone feels they
won't be of any use whatever, and just confuse the picture rather than
clarify it. I have known such perplexity myself a long time ago,
namely in van Kampen-type situations, whose only understandable
formulation is in terms of (amalgamated sums of) groupoids. Still,
standing habits of thought are very strong, and during the long march
through Galois theory, two years ago, it took me weeks and months
trying to formulate everything in terms of groups or ``exterior
groups'' (i.e., groups ``up to inner automorphism''), and finally
learning the lesson and letting myself be convinced progressively, not
to say reluctantly, that groupoids only would fit nicely. Another
``technical point'' of course is the basic fact (and the wealth of
intuitions accompanying it) that the Teichmüller groups are
fundamental groups indeed -- a fact ignored it seems by most
geometers, because the natural ``spaces'' they are fundamental groups
of are not topological spaces, but the modular ``multiplicities''
$M_{g,\nu}$ -- namely topoi! The ``points'' of these ``spaces'' are
just the structures being investigated (namely algebraic curves of
type $(g,\nu)$), and the (finite) automorphism groups of these
``points'' enter into the picture in a very crucial way. They can be
adequately chosen as part of the system of basic generators for the
Teichmüller groupoid $T_{g,\nu}$. The latter of course is essentially
(up to suitable restriction of base-points) just the fundamental
groupoid of $M_{g,\nu}$. It is through this interpretation of the
Teichmüller groups or groupoids that it becomes clear that the
profinite Galois group \GalQQ{} operates on the profinite completion
of these and of their various variants, and this (it turns out) in a
way respecting the manifold structures and relationships tying them
tightly together.
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{29.5.}\pspage{196}\par
% 69
\hangsection[Digression on six weeks' scratchwork: \emph{derivators},
and \dots]{Digression on six weeks' scratchwork:
\texorpdfstring{\emph{derivators}}{derivators}, and integration of
homotopy types.}\label{sec:69}%
Before resuming more technical work again, I would like to have a
short retrospective of the last six weeks' scratchwork, now lying on
my desk as a thickly bunch of scratchnotes, nobody but I could
possibly make any sense of.
The first thing I had on my mind has been there now for nearly twenty
years -- ever since it had become clear, in the SGA~5 seminar on
$L$-functions and apropos the formalism of traces in terms of derived
categories, that Verdier's set-up of derived categories was
insufficient for formulating adequately some rather evident situations
and relationships, such as the addition formula for traces, or the
multiplicative formula for determinants. It then became apparent that
the derived category of an abelian category (say) was too coarse an
object various respects, that it had to be complemented by similar
``triangulated categories'' (such as the derived category of a
suitable category of ``triangles'' of complexes, or the whole bunch of
derived categories of categories of filtered complexes of order $n$
with variable $n$), closely connected to it. Deligne and Illusie had
both set out, independently, to work out some set-up meeting the most
urgent requirements (Illusie's treatment in terms of filtered
complexes was written down and published in his thesis six years later
(Springer Lecture Notes N\textsuperscript{\b o}~239)).%
\scrcomment{\cite{Illusie1971,Illusie1972}}
While adequate for the main tasks then at hand, neither treatment was
really wholly satisfactory to my taste. One main feature I believe
making me feel uncomfortable, was that the extra categories which had
to be introduced, to round up somewhat a stripped-and-naked
triangulated category, were triangulated categories in their own
right, in Verdier's sense, but remaining nearly as stripped by
themselves as the initial triangulated category they were intended to
provide clothing for. In other words, there was a lack of inner
stability in the formalism, making it appear as very much provisional
still. Also, while interested in associating to an abelian category a
handy sequence of ``filtered derived categories'', Illusie made no
attempt to pin down what exactly the inner structure of the object he
had arrived at was -- unlike Verdier, who had introduced, alongside
with the notion of a derived category of an abelian category, a
general notion of triangulated categories, into which these derived
categories would fit. The obvious idea which was in my head by then
for avoiding such shortcomings, was that an abelian category \scrA{}
gave rise, not only to the single usual derived category $D(\scrA)$ of
Verdier, but also, for every type of diagrams,\pspage{197} to the
derived category of the abelian category of all \scrA-valued diagrams
of this type. In precise terms, for any small category $I$, we get the
category $D(\bHom(I,\scrA))$, depending functorially in a
contravariant way on $I$. Rewriting this category $D_\scrA(I)$ say,
the idea was to consider
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:69.star}
I\mapsto D_\scrA(I),\tag{*}
\end{equation}
possibly with $I$ suitably restricted (for instance to finite
categories, or to finite ordered sets, corresponding to finite
\emph{commutative} diagrams), as embodying the ``full'' triangulated
structure defined by \scrA. This of course at once raises a number of
questions, such as recovering the usual triangulated structure of
$D(\scrA)=D_\scrA(e)$ ($e$ the final object of \Cat) in terms of
\eqref{eq:69.star}, and pinning down too the relevant formal
properties (and possibly even extra structure) one had to assume on
\eqref{eq:69.star}. I had never so far taken the time to sit down and
play around some and see how this goes through, expecting that surely
someone else would do it some day and I would be informed -- but
apparently in the last eighteen years nobody ever was
interested. Also, it had been rather clear from the start that
Verdier's constructions could be adapted and did make sense for
non-commutative homotopy set-ups, which was also apparent in between
the lines in Gabriel-Zisman's\scrcomment{\cite{GabrielZisman1967}}
book on the foundations of homotopy theory, and a lot more explicitly
in Quillen's axiomatization of homotopical algebra. This
axiomatization I found very appealing indeed -- and right now still
his little book\scrcomment{\cite{Quillen1967}} is my most congenial
and main source of information on foundational matters of homotopical
algebra. I remember though my being a little disappointed at Quillen's
not caring either to pursue the matter of what exactly a
``non-commutative triangulated category structure'' (of the type he
was getting from his model categories) was, just contenting himself to
mumble a few words about existence of ``higher structure'' (then just
the Dold-Puppe sequences), which (he implies) need to be understood. I
felt of course that presumably the variance formalism
\eqref{eq:69.star} should furnish any kind of ``higher'' structure one
was looking for, but it wasn't really my business to check.
It still isn't, however I did some homework on \eqref{eq:69.star} --
it was the first thing indeed I looked at in these six weeks, and some
main features came out very readily indeed. It turns out that the main
formal variance property to demand on \eqref{eq:69.star}, presumably
even the only one, is that for a given map $f:I\to J$ on the indexing
categories of diagram-types $I$ and $J$, the corresponding functor
\[f^*: D(J) \to D(I)\]
\emph{should have both a left and a right adjoint}, say $f_!$ and
$f_*$. In case $J=e$, the two\pspage{198} functors we get from $D(I)$
to $D(e)=\scrD$ (the ``stripped'' triangulated category) can be viewed
as a \emph{substitute for taking, respectively, direct and inverse
limits in \scrD} (for a system of objects indexed by $I$),
\emph{which in the usual sense don't generally exist in \scrD} (except
just finite sums and products). These operations admit as important
special cases, when $I$ is either one of the two mutually dual
categories
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:69.starstar}
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),column sep=small,row sep=tiny]
& b \\ |[alias=O]| a\ar[ur]\ar[dr] & \\ & c
\end{tikzcd}
\quad\text{or}\quad
\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),column sep=small,row sep=tiny]
& b\ar[dl] \\ |[alias=O]| a & \\ & c\ar[ul]
\end{tikzcd}\quad,\tag{**}
\end{equation}
the operation of (binary) amalgamated sums or fibered products, and
hence also of taking ``cofibers'' and ``fibers'' of maps, in the sense
introduced by Cartan-Serre in homotopy theory about thirty years
ago. I also checked that the two mutually dual Dold-Puppe sequences
follow quite formally from the set-up. One just has to fit in a
suitable extra axiom to ensure the usual exactness properties for
these sequences.
Except in the commutative case when starting with an abelian category
as above, I did not check however that there is indeed such ``higher
variance structure'' in the usual cases, when a typical ``triangulated
category'' in some sense or other turns up, for instance from a model
category in Quillen's sense. What I did check though in this last
case, under a mild additional assumption which seems verified in all
practical cases is the existence of the operation $f_!=\int_I$
(``integration'') and $f_*=\prod_I$ (cointegration) for the special
case $f:I\to e$, when $I$ is either of the two categories
\eqref{eq:69.starstar} above. I expect that working some more, one
should get under the same assumptions at least the existence of $f_!$
and $f_*$ for any map $f:I\to J$ between finite ordered sets.
My main interest of course at present is in the category \Hot{}
itself, more generally in $\HotOf(\scrW)=\scrW^{-1}\Cat$, where
\scrW{} is a ``basic localizer''. More generally, if $(M,W)$ is any
modelizer say, the natural thing to do, paraphrasing
\eqref{eq:69.star}, is for any indexing category $I$ to endow
$\bHom(I,M)$ with the set of arrows $W_I$ defined by componentwise
belonging to $W$, and to define
\[ D_{(M,W)}(I) = D(I) \eqdef W_I^{-1}\bHom(I,M),\]
with the obvious contravariant dependence on $I$, denoted by $f^*$ for
$f:I\to J$. The question then arises as to the existence of left and
right adjoints, $f_!$ and $f_*$. In case we take $M=\Cat$, the
existence of $f_!$ goes through with amazing smoothness: interpreting
a ``model'' object of $\bHom(I,\Cat)$, namely a functor
\[I\to \Cat\]
in\pspage{199} terms of a cofibered category $X$ over $I$
\[p: X\to I,\]
and assuming for simplicity $f$ cofibering too, $f_!(X)$ is just $X$
itself, the total category of the cofibering, viewed as a (cofibered)
category over $J$ by using the functor $g=f\circ p$! This applies for
instance when $J$ is the final category, and yields the operation of
``integration of homotopy types'' $\int_I$, in terms of the total
category of a cofibered category over $I$. If we want to rid ourselves
from any extra assumption on $f$, we can describe $D(I)$ (up to
equivalence) in terms of the category $\Cat_{/I}$ of categories $X$
over $I$ (not necessarily cofibered over $I$), $W_I$ being replaced by
the corresponding notion of ``\emph{\scrW-equivalences relative to
$I$}'' for maps $u:X\to Y$ of objects of \Cat{} over $I$, by which
we mean a map $u$ such that the localized maps
\[u_{/i}: X_{/i} \to Y_{/i}\]
are in \scrW, for any $i$ in $I$. Regarding now any category $X$ over
$I$ as a category over $J$ by means of $f\circ p$, this is clearly
compatible with the relative weak equivalences $\scrW_I$ and
$\scrW_J$, and yields by localization the looked-for functor $f_!$.
This amazingly simple construction and interpretation of the basic
$f_!$ and $\int_I$ operations is one main reward, it appears, for
working with the ``basic localizer'' \Cat, which in this occurrence,
as in the whole test- and asphericity story, quite evidently deserves
its name. It has turned out since that in some other respects -- for
instance, paradoxically when it comes to the question of the
relationship between this lofty integration operation, and true honest
amalgamated sums -- the modelizers \Ahat{} associated to test
categories $A$ (namely the so-called ``elementary modelizers'') are
more convenient tools than \Cat. Thus, it appears very doubtful still
that \Cat{} is a ``model category'' in Quillen's sense, in any
reasonable way (with \scrW{} of course as the set of ``weak
equivalences''). I finally got the feeling that a good mastery of the
basic aspects of homotopy types and of basic relationships among
these, will require mainly great ``aisance''\scrcomment{``aisance''
here could be ``ease'' or ``fluency''} in playing around with a
number of available descriptions of homotopy types by models, no one
among which (not even by models in \Cat, and surely still less by
semisimplicial structures) being adequate for replacing all others.
As for the $f_*$ and cointegration $\prod_I$ operations among the
categories $D(I)$, except in the very special case noted above
(corresponding to fibered products), I did not hit upon any
ready-to-use candidate for it, and I doubt there is any. I do believe
the operations exist indeed, and I even have\pspage{200} in mind a
rather general condition on a pair $(M,W)$ with $W\subset\Fl(M)$, for
both basic operations $f_!$ and $f_*$ to exist between the
corresponding categories $D_{(M,W)}(I)$ -- but to establish this
expectation may require a good amount of work. I'll come back upon
these matters in due course.
There arises of course the question of giving a suitable name to the
structure $I\to D(I)$ I arrived at, which seems to embody at least
some main features of a satisfactory notion of a ``triangulated
category'' (not necessarily commutative), gradually emerging from
darkness. I have thought of calling such a structure a
``\emph{derivator}'', with the implication that its main function is
to furnish us with a somehow ``complete'' bunch (in terms of a
rounded-up self-contained formalism) of categories $D(I)$, which are
being looked at as ``\emph{derived categories}'' in some sense or
other. The only way I know of for constructing such a derivator, is as
above in terms of a pair $(M,W)$, submitted to suitable conditions for
ensuring existence of $f_!$ and $f_*$, at least when $f$ is any map
between finite ordered sets. We may look upon $D(I)$ as a refinement
and substitute for the notion of family of objects of $D(e)=D_0$
indexed by $I$, and the integration and cointegration operations from
$D(I)$ to $D_0$ as substitutes (in terms of these finer objects) of
direct and inverse limits in $D_0$. When tempted to think of these
latter operations (with values in $D_0$) as the basic structures
involved, one cannot help though looking for the same kind of
structure on any one of these subsidiary categories $D(I)$, as these
are being thought of as derived categories in their own right. It then
appears at once that the ``more refined substitutes'' for $J$-indexed
systems of objects of $D(I)$ are just the objects of $D(I\times J)$,
and the corresponding integration and cointegration operations
\[ D(I\times J)\to D(I)\]
are nothing but $p_!$ and $p_*$, where $p:I\times J\to I$ is the
projection. Thus, one is inevitably conducted to look at operations
$f_!$ and $f_*$ instead of merely integration and cointegration --
thus providing for the ``inner stability'' of the structure described,
as I had been looking for from the very start.
The notion of integration of homotopy types appears here as a natural
by-product of an attempt to grasp the ``full structure'' of a
triangulated category. However, I had been feeling the need for such a
notion of integration of homotopy types for about one or two years
already (without any clear idea yet that this operation should be one
out of two\pspage{201} main ingredients of a (by then still very
misty) notion of a triangulated category of sorts). This feeling arose
from my ponderings on stratified structures and the ``screwing
together'' of such structures in terms of simple building blocks
(essentially, various types of ``tubes'' associated to such
structures, related to each other by various proper maps which are
either inclusion or -- in the equisingular case at any rate -- fiber
maps). This ``screwing together operation'' could be expressed as
being a direct limit of a certain finite system of spaces. In the
cases I was most interested in (namely the Mumford-Deligne
compactifications $M\uphat_{g,\nu}$ of the modular multiplicities
$M_{g,\nu}$), these spaces or ``tubes'' have exceedingly simple
homotopy types -- they are just $K(\pi,1)$-spaces, where each $\pi$ is
a Teichmüller-type discrete group (practically, a product of usual
Teichmüller groups). It then occurred to me that the whole homotopy
type of $M\uphat_{g,\nu}$, or of any locally closed union of strata,
or (more generally still) of ``the'' tubular neighborhood of such a
union in any larger one, etc.\ -- that all these homotopy types should
be expressible in terms of the given system of spaces, and more
accurately still, just in terms of the corresponding system of
fundamental groupoids (embodying their homotopy types). In this
situation, what I was mainly out for, was precisely an accurate and
workable description of this direct system of groupoids (which could
be viewed as just one section of the whole ``Teichmüller tower'' of
Teichmüller groupoids\ldots). Thus, it was a rewarding extra feature
of the situation (by then just an expectation, as a matter of fact),
that such a description should at the same time yield a ``purely
algebraic'' description of the homotopy types of all the spaces
(rather, multiplicities, to be wholly accurate) which I could think of
in terms of the natural stratification of $M\uphat_{g,\nu}$. There was
an awareness that this operation on homotopy types could not be
described simply in terms of a functor $I\to\Hot$, where $I$ is the
indexing category, that a functor $i\mapsto X_i: I\to M$ (where $M$ is
some model category such as \Spaces{} or \Cat) should be available in
order to define an ``integrated'' homotopy type $\int X_i$. This
justified feeling got somewhat blurred lately, for a little while, by
the definitely unreasonable expectation that finite limits should
exist in \Hot{} after all, why not! It's enough to have a look though
(which probably I did years ago and then forgot in the meanwhile) to
make sure they don't\ldots
Whether or not this notion of ``integration of homotopy types'' is
more or less well known already under some name or other, isn't quite
clear to me. It isn't familiar to Ronnie Brown visibly, but it seems
he heard about such a kind of thing, without his being specific about
it. It\pspage{202} was the episodic correspondence with him which
finally pushed me last January to sit down for an afternoon and try to
figure out what there actually was, in a lengthy and somewhat rambling
letter to Illusie (who doesn't seem to have heard at all about such
operations). This preliminary reflection proved quite useful lately,
I'll have to come back anyhow upon some of the specific features of
integration of homotopy types later, and there is not much point
dwelling on it any longer at present.
% 70
\hangsection[Digression on scratchwork (2): cohomological
\dots]{Digression on scratchwork
\texorpdfstring{{\normalfont(2)}}{(2)}: cohomological properties of
maps in \texorpdfstring{\Cat}{(Cat)} and in
\texorpdfstring{\Ahat}{Ahat}. Does any topos admit a ``dual'' topos?
Kan fibrations rehabilitated.}\label{sec:70}%
This was a (finally somewhat length!) review of ponderings which
didn't take me more than just a few days, because it was about things
some of which were on my mind for a long time indeed. It took a lot
more work to try to carry through the standard homotopy constructions,
giving rise to the Dold-Puppe sequences, within the basic modelizer
\Cat. Most of the work arose, it now seems to me, out of a block I got
(I couldn't tell why) against the Kan-type condition on complexes, so
I tried hard to get along without anything of the sort. I kind of
fooled myself into believing that I was forced to do so, because I was
working in an axiomatic set-up dependent upon the ``basic localizer''
\scrW, so the Kan condition wouldn't be relevant anyhow. The main
point was to get, for any map $f:X\to Y$ in \Cat, a factorization
\[ X \xrightarrow i Z \xrightarrow p Y,\]
where $p$ has the property that base-change by $p$ transforms weak
equivalences into weak equivalences (visibly a Serre-fibration type
condition), and $i$ satisfies the dual condition with respect to
co-base change; and moreover where either $p$, or $i$ can be assumed
to be in \scrW, i.e., to be a weak equivalence. (This, by the way, is
the extra condition on a pair $(M,W)$ I have been referring to above
(page \ref{p:200}, for (hopefully) getting $f_!$ and $f_*$
operations.) At present, I do not yet know whether such factorization
always exists for a map in \Cat, without even demanding that either
$i$ or $p$ should be in \scrW.
I first devoted a lot of attention to Serre-type conditions on maps in
\Cat, which turned out quite rewarding -- with the impression of
arriving at a coherent and nicely auto-dual picture of cohomology
properties of functors, i.e., maps in \Cat, as far as these were
concerned with \emph{base change behavior} (and \emph{not} co-base
change). Here I was guided by work done long ago to get the étale
cohomology theory off the ground, and where the two main theorems
achieving this aim were precisely two theorems of commutation of
``higher direct images'' $\mathrm R^ig_*$ with respect to base-change
by a map $h$ -- namely, it is OK when either $g$ is \emph{proper}, or
$h$ is \emph{smooth}. It was rather natural then to introduce the
notion of\pspage{203} (cohomological) \emph{smoothness} and (coh.)
\emph{properness} of a map in \Cat, by the obvious base-change
properties. It turned out that these could be readily characterized by
suitable asphericity conditions, which are formally quite similar to
the well-known valuative criterion for a map of finite type between
noetherian schemes to be ``universally open'' (which can be viewed as
a ``purely topological'' variant of the notion of smoothness), resp.\
``universally closed'', or rather, more stringently, proper. These
conditions, moreover, are trivially satisfied when $f: X\to Y$ turns
$X$ into a category over $Y$ which is fibered over $Y$ (i.e.,
definable in terms of a contravariant pseudo-functor $Y\op\to\Cat$),
resp.\ cofibered over $Y$ (namely, definable in terms of a
pseudo-functor $Y\to\Cat$). If we call such maps in \Cat{}
``fibrations'' and ``cofibrations'' (very much in conflict, alas, with
Quillen's neat set-up of fibrations-cofibrations!), it turns out that
\emph{fibrations are smooth}, \emph{cofibrations are proper}. This is
all the more remarkable, as the notions of fibered and cofibered
categories were introduced with a view upon ``large categories'', in
order to pin down some standard properties met in all situations of
``base change'' (and later the dual situation of co-base change) --
the main motivation for this being the need to formulate with a
minimum of precision a set-up for ``descent techniques'' in algebraic
geometry. (These techniques, as well as the cohomological base change
theorems, make visibly a sense too in the context of analytic spaces
say, or of topological spaces, but they don't seem to have been
assimilated yet by geometers outside of algebraic geometry.) That
these typically ``general nonsense'' notions should have such precise
topological implications came as a complete surprise! As a
consequence, a bifibration (namely a map which is both a fibration and
a cofibration) is smooth and proper and hence a (cohomological)
``Serre fibration'', for instance the sheaves $\mathrm R^if_*(F)$,
when $F$ is a constant abelian sheaf on $X$ (i.e., a constant abelian
group object in $X\uphat$), namely $y\mapsto\mathrm H^i(X_{/y},F)$,
are \emph{local systems} on $Y$, i.e., factor through the fundamental
groupoid of $Y$.
A greater surprise still was the \emph{duality between the notions of
properness and smoothness:} just as a map $f:X\to Y$ in \Cat{} is a
cofibration if{f} the ``dual'' map $f\op:X\op\to Y\op$ is a fibration,
it turns out that \emph{$f$ is proper if{f} $f\op$ is smooth}. This
was a really startling fact, and it caused me to wonder, in the
context of more general topoi than just those of the type $X\uphat$,
whether there wasn't \emph{a notion of duality generalizing the
relationship between two topoi $X\uphat$ and $X\upvee \eqdef
(X\op)\uphat$}. Indeed, these two categories of sheaves can be
described intrinsically, one in terms of the other, up to equivalence,
by a natural pairing\pspage{204}
\[X\uphat \times X\upvee \to \Sets\]
commuting componentwise with (small) direct limits, and inducing an
equivalence between either factor with the category of ``co-sheaves''
on the other, namely covariant functors to \Sets{} commuting with
direct limits. But it isn't at all clear, starting with an arbitrary
topos \scrA{} say, whether the category $\scrA'$ of all cosheaves on
\scrA{} is again a topos, and still less whether \scrA{} can be
recovered (up to equivalence) in terms of $\scrA'$ as the category of
all cosheaves on $\scrA'$.
To come back though to the factorization problem raised above (p.\
\ref{p:202}), the main trouble here is that, except the case of an
isomorphism $i: X\tosim Z$, I was unable to pin down a single case of
a map $i$ in \Cat{} such that co-base change by $i$ transforms weak
equivalences (in the usual sense say) into weak equivalences. One
candidate I had in mind, the so-called ``\emph{open immersions}'',
namely functors $i:X\to Z$ inducing an isomorphism between $X$ and a
``sieve'' (or ``crible'') in $Z$ (corresponding to an open sub-topos
of $Z\uphat$), and dually the ``closed immersions'', finally have
turned out delusive -- a disappointment maybe, but still more a big
relief to find out at last how the score was! Almost immediately in
the wake of this negative result in \Cat, and in close connection with
the fairly well understood $\int$ substitute for amalgamated sums in
\Cat, came the big compensation valid in any category $\Ahat$, namely
the fact that for a cocartesian square
\[\begin{tikzcd}
Y\ar[r,"i"] \ar[d,swap,"g"] & X\ar[d,"f"] \\
Y'\ar[r,"i'"] & X'
\end{tikzcd}\]
in \Ahat, where $i$ is a monomorphism, if $i$ (resp.\ $g$) is in
\scrWA, so is $i'$ (resp.\ $f$). This implies that \emph{co-base
change by a monomorphism in \Ahat{} transform weak equivalences into
weak equivalences}. The common main fact behind these statements is
that for a diagram as above (without assuming $i$ nor $g$ to be in
\scrWA), $X'$ can be interpreted up to weak equivalence as the
``integral'' of the diagram
\[\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),sep=small]
Y\ar[r] \ar[d] & X \\
|[alias=O]| Y' &
\end{tikzcd},\]
more accurately, the natural map in \Cat
\[\int \begin{tikzcd}[cramped,sep=small]
A_{/Y}\ar[r]\ar[d] & A_{/X} \\ A_{/Y'} &
\end{tikzcd} \longrightarrow\; A_{/X'}\]
is in \scrW.
The corresponding statement in \Cat{} itself, even if $i$ is
supposed\pspage{205} to be an open immersion in \Cat{} say (or a
closed immersion, which amounts to the same by duality), is definitely
false, in other words: while the modelizer \Cat{} allows for a
remarkably simple description of integration of homotopy types, as
seen in the previous section, in the basic case however of an
integration\scrcomment{this integral is set inline in the typescript}
\[\int \begin{tikzcd}[cramped,sep=small]
A_{/Y}\ar[r,"i"]\ar[d,"g"] & A_{/X} \\ A_{/Y'} &
\end{tikzcd}\]
(corresponding to ``amalgamated sums''), and even when $i:Y\to X$ is
an open or closed immersion, this operation does definitely \emph{not}
correspond to the operation of taking the amalgamated sum $X'$ in
\Cat. It does though when $X\to X'$ is smooth resp.\ proper, for
instance if it is a fibration resp.\ a cofibration, and this in fact
implies the positive result in \Ahat{} noted above. This condition
moreover is satisfied if $g: Y\to Y'$ is equally an open resp.\ closed
immersion, in which case the situation is just the one of an ambient
$X'$, and two open resp.\ closed subobjects $X$ and $Y'$, with
intersection $Y$. This is a useful result, but wholly insufficient for
the factorization problem we were after in \Cat, with a view of
performing the standard homotopy constructions in \Cat{} itself. It
may be true still that if $i:Y\to X$ is not only an open or closed
immersion, but a weak equivalence as well, that then $i':Y'\to X'$ is
equally a weak equivalence, or what amounts to the same, that $X'$ can
be identified up to weak equivalence with the homotopy integral (which
indeed, up to weak equivalence, just reduces to $Y'$); but I have been
unable so far to clear up this matter. If true, this would be quite a
useful result, but still insufficient it seems in order to carry out
the standard homotopy constructions in \Cat{} itself.
To sum up, the main drawback of \Cat{} as a modelizer is that, except
in very special cases which are just too restricted, amalgamated sums
in \Cat{} don't have a reasonable meaning in terms of homotopy
operations -- whereas in a category \Ahat, a topos indeed where
therefore amalgamated sums have as good exactness properties as if
working in \Sets, these amalgamated sums (for a two-arrow diagram with
one arrow a monomorphism) \emph{do} have a homotopy-theoretic
meaning. This finally seems to force us, in order to develop some of
the basic structure in $\HotOf(\scrW)$, to leave the haven of the
basic modelizer \Cat, and work in an elementary modelizer \Ahat{}
instead, where $A$ is some \scrW-test category. This then brought me
back finally to the question whether these modelizers are \emph{closed
model categories} in Quillen's sense, when we take of course for
``weak equivalences'' \scrWA, and moreover as ``cofibrations'' (in the
sense of Quillen's set-up) just the monomorphisms. Relying heavily
upon the result on monomorphisms in \Ahat{} stated above, it seems to
come out that we do get a closed model category indeed -- and even a
simplicial model category, if we are out for this. There is still a
cardinality question to be\pspage{206} settles to get the Quillen
factorizations in the general case, but this should not be too serious
a difficulty I feel. What however makes me still feel a little unhappy
in all this, is rather that I did not get a direct proof for an
elementary modelizer being a closed model category -- I finally have
to make a reduction to the known case of semisimplicial complexes,
settles by Quillen in his notes. This detour looks rather artificial
-- it is the first instance, and presumably the last one, where the
theory I am digging out seems to depend on semi-simplicial techniques,
techniques which moreover I don't really know and am not really eager
to swallow. It's just a prejudice maybe, a block maybe against the
semi-simplicial approach which I never really liked nor assimilated --
but I do have the feeling that the more refined and specific
semi-simplicial techniques and notions (such as minimal fibrations,
used in Quillen's proof, alas!) are irrelevant for an understanding of
the main structures featuring homotopy theory and homotopical
algebra. As for the notion of a Kan complex or a Kan fibration --
namely just a ``fibration'' in Quillen's axiomatic set-up, which I was
finally glad to find, ``ready for use'' -- I came to convince myself
at last that it was a basic notion indeed, and it was no use trying to
bypass it at all price. Thus, I took to the opposite, and tried to pin
down a Quillen-type factorization theorem, and his characteristic
seesaw game between right and left lifting properties, in as great
generality as I could manage.
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{30.5.}\par
% 71
\hangsection[Working program and rambling questions (group objects
\dots]{Working program and rambling questions \texorpdfstring{\textup
(}{(}group objects as models, Dold-Puppe
theorem\ldots\texorpdfstring{\textup )}{)}.}\label{sec:71}%
The scratchwork done since last month has of course considerably
cleared up the prospects of my present pre-stacks reflection on
homotopy models, on which I unsuspectingly embarked three months
ago. I would like to sketch a provisional working program for the
notes still ahead.
\namedlabel{it:71.A}{A)} Write down at last the story of asphericity
structures and canonical modelizers, as I was about to when I
interrupted the notes to do my scratchwork.
\namedlabel{it:71.B}{B)} Study the basic modelizer \Cat, and the
common properties of elementary modelizers \Ahat, with a main emphasis
upon base change and co-base change properties, and upon Quillen-type
factorization questions. Here it will be useful to dwell somewhat on
the ``homotopy integral'' variant of taking amalgamated sums in \Cat,
on the analogous constructions for topoi, and how these compare to the
usual amalgamated sums, including the interesting case of topological
spaces. It turns out that the homotopy\pspage{207} integral variant
for amalgamated sums is essentially characterized by a Mayer-Vietoris
type long exact sequence for cohomology, and the cases when the
homotopy construction turns out to be equivalent to usual amalgamated
sums, are just those when such a Mayer-Vietoris sequence exists for
the latter. An interesting and typical case is for topological spaces,
taking the amalgamated sum for a diagram
\[\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),sep=small]
Y\ar[r,hook,"i"] \ar[d,swap,"g"] & X \\
|[alias=O]| Y' &
\end{tikzcd},\]
when $i$ is a closed immersion and $g$ is proper (which is also the
basic type of amalgamations which occur in the ``unfolding'' of
stratified structures).
In the course of the last weeks' reflections, there has taken place
also a substantial clarification concerning the relevant properties of
a basic localizer \scrW{} and how most of these, including strong
saturation of \scrW, follow from just the first three (a question which
kept turning up like a nuisance throughout the notes!). This should be
among the very first things to write down in this part of the
reflections, as \scrW{} after all is \emph{the} one axiomatic data
upon which the whole set-up depends.
\namedlabel{it:71.C}{C)}\enspace A reflection on the main common features of
the various contexts met with so far having a ``homotopy theory''
flavor, with a hope to work out at least some of the main features of
an all-encompassing new structure, along the lines of Verdier's
(commutative) theory of derived categories and triangulated
categories. The basic idea here, for the time being, seems to be the
notion of a \emph{derivator}, which should account for all the kind of
structure dealt with in Verdier's set-up, as well as in Deligne's and
Illusie's later elaborations. There seems to be however some important
extra features which are not accounted for by the mere derivator, such
as external $\Hom$'s with values in \Hot{} or some closely related
category, and the formalism of basic invariants (such as $\pi_i$,
$\mathrm H_i$ or $\mathrm H^i$), with values in suitable categories
(often abelian ones), which among others allow to check weak
equivalence. Such features seem to be invariably around in all cases I
know of, and they need to be understood I feel.
Coming back to \Hot{} itself and to modelizers $(M,W)$ giving rise to
it, there is the puzzling question about when exactly can we assert
that taking group objects of $M$ and weak equivalences between these
(namely group-object homomorphisms which are also in $W$), we get by
localization a category equivalent to the category of pointed
$0$-connected homotopy types. This is a well-known basic fact when we
take as models semisimplicial complexes or (I guess) topological
spaces -- a fact closely connected to the game of
associating\pspage{208} to any topological group its
``\emph{classifying space}'', defined ``up to homotopy''. I suspect
the same should hold in any elementary modelizer \Ahat, $A$ a test
category, at least in the ``strict'' case, namely when \Ahat{} is
totally aspheric, i.e., the canonical functor $\Ahat\to\Hot$ commutes
to finite products. The corresponding statement for the basic
localizer \Cat{} itself is definitely false. Group objects in \Cat{}
are indeed very interesting and well-known beings (introduced, I
understand from Ronnie Brown, by Henry Whitehead long time ago, under
the somewhat misleading name of ``crossed modules''), yet they embody
not arbitrary pointed $0$-connected homotopy types $X$, but merely those
for which $\pi_i(X)=0$ for $i>2$. Thus, we get only $2$-truncated
homotopy types -- and presumably, starting with $n\mathrm{-Cat}$
instead of \Cat{} as a modelizer, we then should get $(n+1)$-truncated
homotopy types. This ties in with the observation that taking group
objects either in \Cat, or in the full subcategory
$(\mathrm{Groupoids})$ of the latter, amounts to the same -- and
similarly surely for $(n\mathrm{-Cat})$; on the other hand it has been
kind of clear from the very beginning of this reflection that at any
\emph{finite} level, groupoids and $n$-groupoids ($n$ finite) will
only yield \emph{truncated} homotopy types.
A related intriguing question is when exactly does a modelizer $(M,W)$
give rise to a \emph{Dold-Puppe theorem} -- namely when do we get an
actual \emph{equivalence} between the category of \emph{abelian} group
objects of $M$, and the category of chain complexes of abelian groups?
The original statement was in case $M=\Simplexhat=$ semisimplicial
complexes, and doubtlessly it was one main impetus for the sudden
invasion of homotopy and cohomology by semisimplicial calculus -- so
much so it seems that for many people, ``homotopy'' has become
synonymous to ``semisimplicial algebra''. The impression that
semi-simplicial complexes is the God-given ground for doing homotopy
and even cohomology, comes out rather strong also in Quillen's
foundational notes, and in Illusie's thesis. Still, there are too some
cubical theory chaps I heard, who surely must have noticed long ago
that the Dold-Puppe theorem is valid equally for cubical complexes (I
could hardly imagine that it possibly couldn't). Now it turns out that
semisimplicial and cubical complexes are part of a trilogy, together
with so-called ``\emph{hemispherical complexes}'',\scrcomment{I guess
today we call these ``globular sets''} which look at lot simpler
still, with just two boundary operators and one degeneracy in each
dimension. They can be viewed as embodying the ``primitive structure''
of an \oo-groupoid, the boundary operators being the ``source'' and
``target'' maps, and the degeneracy the map associating to any