-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 13
/
Copy pathps3.tex
5125 lines (4877 loc) · 265 KB
/
ps3.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
%% Anti-Copyright 2015 - the scrivener
\chapter{Grinding my way towards canonical modelizers}
\label{ch:III}
\presectionfill\ondate{27.3.}\pspage{89}\par
% 45
\hangsection[It's burning again! Review of some ``recurring striking
\dots]{It's burning again! Review of some ``recurring striking
features'' of modelizers and standard modelizing functors.}%
\label{sec:45}%
The review yesterday of the various ``test notions'', turning around
test categories and test functors, turned out a lot longer than
expected, so much so to have me get a little weary by the end -- it
was clear though that this ``travail d'intendance'' was necessary, not
only not to get lost in a morass of closely related and yet definitely
distinct notions, but also to gain perspective and a better feeling of
the formal structure of the whole set-up. As has been the case so
often, during the very work of ``grinding through'', there has
appeared this characteristic feeling of getting close to something
``burning'' again, something very simple-minded surely which has kept
showing up gradually and more and more on all odds and ends, and which
still is escaping, still elusive. These is an impressive bunch of
things which are demanding pressingly more or less immediate
investigation -- still I can't help, I'll have to try and pin down
some way or other this ``burning spot''.
There seem to be recurring striking features of the modelizers met
with so far -- namely essentially \Cat{} and the elementary modelizers
\Ahat{} and possibly their ``weak'' variants. In all of them, these is
a very strong interplay between the following notions, which seem to
be the basic ones and more or less determine each other mutually:
\emph{weak equivalences} (which define the modelizing structure of the
given modelizer $M$), \emph{aspheric objects} (namely such that
$x\to e_M$ is a weak equivalence), \emph{homotopy intervals}
$(I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$, and last not least, the notion of a test
functor $A \to M$, where $A$ is a test category (or more generally
weak test functors of weak test categories into $M$). The latter so
far have been defined only when $M=\Cat$, and initially they were
viewed as being mainly more handy substitutes to $j_A$, for getting a
model-preserving functor $\Cat\to\Ahat$ quasi-inverse to the
all-important model-preserving functor $i_A:\Ahat\to\Cat$,
$F\mapsto A_{/F}$. I suspect however that their role is a considerably
more basic one than just computational convenience -- and this reminds
me of the analogous feeling I had, when first contemplating using such
a thing as (by then still vaguely conceived) ``test categories'', for
investigating ways of putting modelizing structures on categories $M$
such as categories of algebraic structures of some kind or
other. (Cf.\ notes of \hyperref[date:7.3.]{March 7}, and more
specifically par.\ \ref{sec:26} -- this was the very day, by the way,
I first had this feeling of being ``burning''\ldots)
Test\pspage{90} categories seem to play a similar role here as (the
spectra of) discrete valuation rings in algebraic geometry -- they can
be mapping into anywhere, to ``test'' what is going on there -- here
it means, they can be sent into any modelizer $(M,W)$ (at least among
the ones which we feel are the most interesting), by ``test functors''
$i:A\to M$ giving rise to a model-preserving functor $i^*:M\to\Ahat$,
allowing comparison of $M$ with an elementary modelizer $\Ahat$. As
for the all-encompassing basic modelizer \Cat, it seems to play the
opposite role in a sense, at least with respect to elementary
modelizers, \Ahat, which all admit modelizing maps
$i_A:\Ahat\to\Cat$. As a matter of fact, for given test category $A$,
i.e., a given elementary modelizer \Ahat, I see for the time being
just \emph{one} way to get a modelizing functor from it to \Cat,
namely just the canonical $i_A$. There is also a striking difference
between the exactness properties of the functors
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.1}
i^*:M\to\Ahat\tag{1}
\end{equation}
one way, which commute to inverse limits, and the functors
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.2}
i_A:\Ahat\to\Cat\tag{2}
\end{equation}
in the other direction, commuting to direct limits. Another difference
is that we should not expect that the left adjoint $i_!$ to $i^*$ be
model preserving too (with the exception of the very special case when
$M=\Cat$ and $i:A\to M=\Cat$ is the canonical functor $i_A\restrto A$,
which appears as highly non-typical in this respect), whereas the
right adjoint $j_A=i_A^*$ of $i_A$ is model preserving, this $i_A$ is
part of a pair $(i_A,j_A)$ of model preserving adjoint functors.
Of course, we may want to compare directly an arbitrary modelizer $M$
to \Cat{} by sending it into \Cat{} by a modelizing functor
$M\to\Cat$; we get quite naturally such a functor (for any given
choice of test-functor $i:A\to M$)
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.3}
i_Ai^*: M \to \Cat,\tag{3}
\end{equation}
but this functor is not likely any more to commute neither to direct
nor inverse limits, even finite ones -- and it isn't too clear that
for a modelizer $M$ which isn't elementary, we have much chance to get
a modelizing functor to \Cat{} which is either left or right
exact. However, the functors \eqref{eq:45.3} we've got, whenever
modelizing and if $M$ is a \emph{strict} modelizer (namely $M\to
W_M^{-1}M\simeq\Hot$ commutes with finite products), will commute to
finite products ``up to weak equivalence''. Also the functors $i^*$,
although not right exact definitely, have a tendency to commute to
sums, and hence the same will hold (not only up to weak equivalence)
for \eqref{eq:45.3}.
As for getting a modelizing functor $\Cat\to M$, for a modelizer
$M$\pspage{91} which isn't elementary, in view of having a standard
way for describing a given homotopy type (defined by an object $C$ in
\Cat) by a ``model'' in $M$, depending functorially on $C$, there
doesn't seem to be any general process for finding one, even without
any demand on exactness properties, except of course when $M$ is
supposed to be elementary; in this case $M=\Ahat$ we get the functors
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.4}
i^*:\Cat\to\Ahat\tag{4}
\end{equation}
associated to test functors $A\to\Cat$, which can be viewed as a
particular case of \eqref{eq:45.1}, applied to the case
$M=\Cat$. Using such functors \eqref{eq:45.4}, we see that the
question of finding a modelizing functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.star}
\varphi: \Cat\to M,\tag{*}
\end{equation}
for a more or less general $M$, is tied up with the question of
finding such a functor from an elementary modelizer \Ahat{} into $M$
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.starstar}
\psi:\Ahat\to M.\tag{**}
\end{equation}
More specifically, if we got a $\psi$, we deduce a $\varphi$ by
composing with $i^*$ in \eqref{eq:45.4}, and conversely, if we got a
$\varphi$, we deduce a $\psi$ by composing with the canonical functor
$i_A$ in \eqref{eq:45.2}. Maybe it's unrealistic to expect modelizing
functors \eqref{eq:45.star} or \eqref{eq:45.starstar} to exist for
rather general $M$. (Which modelizers will turn out to be really ``the
interesting ones'' will appear in due course presumably\ldots) There
is one interesting case though when we got such functors, namely when
\[M=\Spaces\]
is the category of topological spaces, and taking for $\psi$ one of
the manifold avatars of ``geometric realization functor'', associated
to a suitable functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.starstarstar}
r:A\to\Spaces\tag{***}
\end{equation}
by taking the canonical extension $r_!$ to \Ahat, commuting with
direct limits. This is precisely the ``highly non-typical'' case, when
we get a pair of adjoint functors $r_!,r^*$
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.5}
\begin{tikzcd}
\Ahat\ar[r, shift left, "r_!"] & \Spaces\ar[l, shift left, "r^*"]
\end{tikzcd}\tag{5}
\end{equation}
which are \emph{both} modelizing. The situation here mimics very
closely the situation of the pair $(i_A,j_A=i_A^*)$ canonically
associated to the elementary modelizer \Ahat, with the ``basic modelizer''
\Cat{} being replaced by \Spaces, which therefore can be considered as
another ``basic modelizer'' of sorts. In this case the corresponding
functor
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:45.6}
r_!r^* : \Cat\to\Spaces
\tag{6}
\end{equation}
mimics the functor $i_Ai^*$ of \eqref{eq:45.3} (where on the left hand
side $M$ is taken to be just \Cat, and on the right \Cat{} as the
basic modelizer is replaced by its next best substitute \Spaces). Here
as in \eqref{eq:45.3}, the modelizing functor we got is neither left
nor right exact, it has a tendency\pspage{92} though to commute to
sums, as usual.
I wouldn't overemphasize the capacity of \Spaces{} to serve the
purpose of a ``basic modelizer'' as does \Cat, despite the attractive
feature of more direct (or at any rate, more conventional) ties with
so-called ``topological intuition''. One drawback of \Spaces{} is the
relative sophistication of the structure species ``topological
spaces'' it corresponds to, which is by no means an ``algebraic
structure species'', and fits into algebraic formalisms only at the
price of detours. More seriously still, or rather as a reflection of
this latter feature, only for some rather special elementary
modelizers \Ahat, namely rather special test categories $A$, do we get
a geometric realization functor $r_!:\Ahat\to\Spaces$ which can be
view as part of a pair of mutually adjoint modelizing functors,
mimicking the canonical pair $(i_A,j_A)$; still less does there seem
to be anything like a really canonical choice (although some choices
are pretty natural indeed, dealing with the standard test categories
such as $\Simplex$ and its variants). At any rate, it is still to be
seen whether there exists such a pair $(r_!,r^*)$ for some rather
general class of test categories -- this is one among the very many
things that I keep pushing off, as more urgent matters are calling for
attention\ldots
To sum up the outcome of these informal reflections about various
types of modelizing functors between modelizers, the two main types
which seem to overtower the whole picture, and are likely to be the
essential ones for a general understanding of homotopy models, are the
two types \eqref{eq:45.1} and \eqref{eq:45.2} above. The first one
$i^*$ is defined in terms of an arbitrary modelizer $M$. The second
$i_A$, with opposite exactness properties to the previous one, is
canonically attached to any test category, and maps the corresponding
elementary modelizer \Ahat{} into the basic modelizer \Cat, without
any reference to more general types of modelizers $M$. The right
adjoint of the latter, which is still model preserving, is in fact of
the type \eqref{eq:45.1} again, for the canonical test functor
$A\to\Cat$ induced by $i_A$, namely $a\mapsto A_{/a}$.
This whole reflection was of course on such an informal level, that
there was no sense at that stage to bother with distinctions between
weaker or stricter variants of the test-notion. Maybe it's about time
now to start getting a little more specific.\pspage{93}
% 46
\hangsection[Test functors with values in any modelizer: an
\dots]{Test functors with values in any modelizer: an observation,
with an inspiring ``silly question''.}\label{sec:46}%
First thing to do visibly is to define the notion of a test-functor
\[ i : A \to M,\]
where $M$ is any modelizer. Thus $M$ is endowed with a subset
$W_M\subset\Fl(M)$, i.e., a notion of weak equivalence, satisfying the
``mild saturation conditions'' of p.\ \ref{p:59}, and moreover we
assume that $W_M^{-1}M$ is equivalent to \Hot{} -- but the choice of
an equivalence, or equivalently, of the corresponding localization
functor
\[ M \to \Hot,\]
is not given with the structure. (If we admit the ``inspiring
assumption'', there is no real choice, as a matter of fact -- but we
don't want to use this in a technical sense, but only as a guide and
motivation.)
Let's start with the weak variant -- we assume $A$ to be a weak test
category, and want to define what it means that $i$ is a \emph{weak
test functor}. In all this game, it is understood that in case
$M=\Cat$, the notions we want to define (of a weak test functor and of
a test functor) should reduce to the ones we have pinpointed in
yesterday's notes.
The very first idea that comes to mind, is to demand merely that the
corresponding $i^*$ \eqref{eq:45.1}
\[ i^*: M\to\Ahat\]
should be modelizing, which means (I recall)
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*)]
\item $W_M= (i^*)^{-1}(W_A)$.
\item The induced functor $W_M^{-1}M \to W_A^{-1}\Ahat$ is an
equivalence.
\end{enumerate}
This, I just checked, does correspond to the definition we gave
yesterday (p.\ \ref{p:85}), when $M=\Cat$. There is a very interesting
extra feature though in this special case, which appears kind of ``in
between the lines'' in the ``\hyperref[thm:keyresult]{key result}'' on
p.\ \ref{p:61}, and which I want now to state in the more general
set-up.
As usual in related situations, the notion of weak equivalence in $M$
gives rise to a corresponding notion of ``aspheric'' elements in $M$
-- namely those for which the unique map
\[x \to e_M\]
is a weak equivalence. We assume now the existence of a final object
$e_M$ in $M$, and will assume too, if necessary, that it's the image
in the localization $W_M^{-1}M= H_M$ is equally a final object. Thus,
if $x$ in $M$ is aspheric, its image in $H_M$ is a final object, and
the converse holds provided as assume $W_M$ strongly saturated, namely
any map in $M$ which becomes an isomorphism in $H_M$ is a weak
equivalence.\footnote{\alsoondate{29.3.} This assumption will be verified if there
exists a weak test functor $i:A\to M$.}
I\pspage{94} can now state the ``interesting extra feature''.
\begin{observation}
For a functor $i:A\to M$ of a weak test category $A$ into the
modelizer $M$ \textup(with final object $e_M$, giving rise to the
final object in $H_M=W_M^{-1}M$\textup), and in the special case
when $M=\Cat$, the following conditions are equivalent:
\begin{enumerate}[label=(\roman*),font=\normalfont]
\item\label{it:46.i}
$i^*$ transforms weak equivalence into weak equivalences,
i.e., induces a functor $H_M\to H_\Ahat$.
\item\label{it:46.ii}
$i^*$ transforms aspheric objects into aspheric objects.
\item\label{it:46.iii}
$i$ is a weak test functor, namely $W_M=(i^*)^{-1}(W_\Ahat)$
\textup(a stronger version of \textup{\ref{it:46.i}}\textup)
\emph{and} the induced functor $H_M\to H_\Ahat$ is an \emph{equivalence}.
\end{enumerate}
\end{observation}
Here the obvious implications are of course
\[ \text{\ref{it:46.iii}} \Rightarrow \text{\ref{it:46.i}} \Rightarrow
\text{\ref{it:46.ii},}\]
the second implication coming from the fact that $i^*$ is compatible
with final objects, and that $e_\Ahat$ is aspheric. Of course,
\ref{it:46.ii} means that for any aspheric $x$ in $M$, $A_{/i^*(x)}$
is aspheric in \Cat. In case $M=\Cat$, and when moreover the elements
$i(a)$ in \Cat{} have final objects (a condition I forgot to include
in the statement of the observation above, sorry), this condition was
seen to imply \ref{it:46.iii} (cf.\ ``\hyperref[thm:keyresult]{key result}'' on
p.\ \ref{p:61}, \hyperref[it:key.a.iv]{(a~iv)} $\Rightarrow$
\hyperref[it:key.a.ii]{(a~ii)} -- indeed, it is even enough to check
that for any $C$ \emph{with final element} in \Cat, $i^*(C)$ is
aspheric. The proof moreover turns out practically trivial, in terms
of the usual \ref{lem:asphericitycriterion} for a functor between
categories. So much so that the really amazing strength of the
statement, which appears clearly when looked at in a more general
setting, as I just did, was kind of blurred by the impression of
merely fastidiously grinding through routine equivalences. We got
there at any rate quite an interesting class of functors between
modelizers (an elementary and the basic one, for the time being), for
which the mere fact that the functor be compatible with weak
equivalences, or only even take aspheric objects into aspheric ones,
implies that the functor in modelizing, namely that the functor
$H_M\to H_\Ahat$ it induces (and the very \emph{existence} of this
functor was all we demanded beforehand!) is actually an
\emph{equivalence of categories}.
The question that immediately comes to mind now, is if this ``extra
feature'' is indeed an extremely special one, strongly dependent on
the assumption $M=\Cat$ and the categories $i(a)$ having final objects
-- or if it may not have a considerably wider significance. This
suggests the still more general questions, involving two modelizers
$M,M'$, neither of which needs by elementary or by \Cat{}
itself:\pspage{95}
\begin{question}\label{q:naivequestion}
Let
\[f : M\to M'\]
be a functor between modelizers $(M,W)$ and $(M',W')$, assume if
needed that $f$ commute with inverse limits, or even has a left
adjoint, and that inverse limits (and direct ones too, as for that!)
exist in $M,M'$. Are there some natural conditions we can devise for
$M$ and $M'$ (which should be satisfied for elementary modelizers
and for the basic modelizer \Cat), plus possibly some mild extra
conditions on $f$ itself, which will ensure that whenever $f$
transforms weak equivalences into weak equivalences, or even only
aspheric objects into aspheric objects, $f$ is model-preserving,
i.e., $W_M = f^{-1}(W_{M'})$ \emph{and} the induced functor
$H_f:H_M\to H_{M'}$ on the localizations is an equivalence of categories?
\end{question}
Maybe it's a silly question, with pretty obvious negative answer -- in
any case, I'll have to find out! The very first thing to check is to
see what happens in case of a functor
\[i^*:M\to\Ahat,\]
where \Ahat{} is a weak elementary modelizer, and where $M$ is either
\Cat{} or another weak elementary modelizer $B\uphat$, $i^*$ in any
case being associated of course to a functor
\[i:A\to M,\]
with a priori no special requirement whatever on $i$. In case
$M=\Cat$, this means looking up in the end the question we have
postponed for quite a while now, namely of how to rescue the
``\hyperref[thm:keyresult]{key result}'' of p.\ \ref{p:61}, when
dropping the assumption that the categories $i(a)$ (for $a$ in $A$)
have final objects. We finally got a strong motivation for carrying
through a generalization, if this is indeed feasible.
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{30.3.}\par
% 47
\hangsection[An approach for handling \Cat-valued test functors, and
\dots]{An approach for handling \texorpdfstring{\Cat}{(Cat)}-valued
test functors, and promise of a ``key result'' revised. The
significance of contractibility.}\label{sec:47}%
It had become clear that the most urgent thing to do now was to come
to a better understanding of test functors with values in \Cat, when
dropping the assumption that the categories $i(a)$ have final objects,
and trying to replace this (if it should turn out that something
\emph{is} needed indeed) by a kind of assumption which should make
sense when \Cat{} is replaced by a more or less arbitrary modelizer
$M$. I spent a few hours pondering over the situation, and it seems to
me that in the case at least when $A$ is a \emph{strict}, namely when
\Ahat{} is totally aspheric, there is now a rather complete
understanding of the situation, with a generalization of the
``\hyperref[thm:keyresult]{key result}'' of p.\ \ref{p:61} which seems
to be wholly satisfactory.
The\pspage{96} basic idea of how to handle the more general situation,
namely how to compare the categories $A_{/i^*(C)}=A_{/C}$ and $C$, and
show (under suitable assumptions) that there is a canonical
isomorphism between their images in the localized category
$W_\Cat^{-1}\Cat=\Hot$, was around since about the moment I worked out
the ``key result''. It can be expressed by a diagram of ``maps'' in
\Cat
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:47.1}
\begin{tikzcd}[cramped]
A_{/C} \ar[r] & A_{\sslash C} & \\
& A\times C \ar[u]\ar[r] & C\quad,
\end{tikzcd}
\tag{1}
\end{equation}
where $A_{\sslash C}$ is the fibered category over $A$, associated to
the functor
\[ A\op\to\Cat, \quad a\mapsto\bHom(i(a),C).\]
Here one should be careful with the distinction between the \emph{set}
\[ \Hom(i(a),C) = \Ob \bHom(i(a),C),\]
and the \emph{category} $\bHom(i(a),C)$, both depending
bi-functorially on $a$ in $A$ and $C$ in \Cat. The former (as a
presheaf on $A$ for fixed $C$) gives rise to $A_{/C}$, a fibered
category over $A$ with \emph{discrete} fibers, whereas the latter
gives rise to $A_{\sslash C}$, which is fibered over $A$ with fibers
that need not be discrete. Identifying a set with the discrete
category it defines, we get a canonical functor
\[ \Hom(i(a),C) \to \bHom(i(a),C),\]
which is very far from being an equivalence nor even a weak
equivalence; being functorial for varying $a$, it gives rise to the
first map in \eqref{eq:47.1}. The second is deduced from the canonical
functor
\[C \to \bHom(i(a),C),\]
identifying $C$ with the full subcategory of \emph{constant} functors
from $i(a)$ to $C$. This map is functorial in $a$, and gives rise
again to a cartesian functor between the corresponding fibered
categories over $A$, the first one (which corresponds to the constant
functor $A\op\to\Cat$ with value $C$) is just $A\times C$ fibered over
$A$ by $\pr_1$, hence the second arrow in \eqref{eq:47.1}. The third
arrow is just $\pr_2$.
It seems that, with the introduction of $A_{\sslash C}$, this is the
first time since the beginning of these reflections that we are making
use of the \emph{bicategory structure} of \Cat, namely of the notion
of a morphism or map or ``homotopy'' (the tie with actual homotopies
will be made clear below), between two ``maps'' namely (here) functors
$C'\rightrightarrows C$. There is of course a feeling that such a
notion of homotopy should make sense in a more or less arbitrary
modelizer $M$, and that the approach displayed by the diagram
\eqref{eq:47.1} may well generalize to mere general
situations\pspage{97} still, with \Cat{} replaced by such an $M$.
In the situation here, the work will consist in devising handy
conditions on $i: A\to\Cat$ and $A$ that will ensure that all three
maps in \eqref{eq:47.1} are weak equivalences, for any choice of
$C$. This will imply that the corresponding maps in \Hot{} are
isomorphisms, hence a canonical isomorphism between the images in
\Hot{} of $A_{/C}$ and $C$, which will imply that a)\enspace the
functor $i_Ai^*$ from \Cat{} to \Cat{} carries weak equivalences into
weak equivalences, and hence induces a functor
\[\Hot\to\Hot,\]
and b)\enspace that this functor is isomorphic to the identity
functor. If moreover $A$ is a weak test category, and therefore the
functor
\[W_A^{-1}\Ahat\to\Hot\]
induced by $i_A$ is an equivalence, it will follow that the functor
\[\Hot\to W_A^{-1}\Ahat\]
induced by $i^*$ is equally an equivalence, namely that $i^*$ is
indeed a test-functor.
For the map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:47.2}
A\times C\to C
\tag{2}
\end{equation}
to be a weak equivalence for any $C$ in \Cat, it is necessary and
sufficient that $A$ be aspheric (cf.\ par.\ \ref{sec:40}, page
\ref{p:69}), a familiar condition on $A$ indeed! For handling the map
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:47.3}
A\times C\to A_{\sslash C}\quad\text{associated to $C\to\bHom(i(a),C)$,}
\tag{3}
\end{equation}
we'll use the following easy result (which I'll admit for the time
being):
\begin{proposition}
Let $F$ and $G$ be two categories over a category $A$\kern1pt, and $u:F\to
G$ a functor compatible with projections. We assume
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*),font=\normalfont]
\item\label{it:47.a}
For any $a$ in $A$\kern1pt, the induced map on the fibers
\[u_a : F_a \to G_a\]
is a weak equivalence.
\item\label{it:47.b}
Either $F$ and $G$ are both cofibering over $A$ and $u$ is
cocartesian, or $F$ and $G$ are fibering and $u$ is cartesian.
\end{enumerate}
Then $u$ is a weak equivalence.
\end{proposition}
This shows that a sufficient condition for \eqref{eq:47.3} to be a
weak equivalence, is that the functors $C\to\bHom(i(a),C)$ be a weak
equivalence, for any $a$ in $A$ and $C$ in \Cat. We'll see in the next
section\footnote{\alsoondate{9.4.} Actually, this is done only a lot later, on page
\ref{p:121} and (for the converse) on page \ref{p:143}.} that this
amounts to demanding that the objects $i(a)$ in \Cat{} should be
``contractible'', in the most concrete sense of this expression, which
is actually stronger than just asphericity. (Earlier in these notes I
was a little floppy with the terminology, by using a few times the
word ``contractible''\pspage{98} as synonymous to ``aspheric'' as in
the context of topological spaces, or CW spaces at any rate, the two
notions do indeed coincide, finally I came to use rather the word
``aspheric'' systematically, as it fits nicely with the notion of an
aspheric morphism of topos\ldots) The most evident example of
contractible categories are the categories with final object. Thus I
have the strong feeling that the condition of contractibility of the
objects $i(a)$ in \Cat{} is ``the right'' generalization of the
assumption made in the ``key result'', namely that the $i(a)$ have
final elements. Also, it seems now likely that the numerous cases of
statements, when to check some property for arbitrary $C$, it turned
out to be enough to check it for $C$ with a final object, may well
generalize to more general cases, with \Cat{} replaced by some $M$ and
the reduction is from arbitrary $C$ in $M$ to contractible ones.
The next thing to do is to develop a little the notion of
contractibility of objects and of homotopies between maps, and to get
the criterion just announced for \eqref{eq:47.3} to be a weak
equivalence for any $C$. After this, handling the question of the
first map in \eqref{eq:47.1}
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:47.4}
A_{/C} \to A_{\sslash C}
\tag{4}
\end{equation}
being a weak equivalence for any $C$, in terms of the
\ref{lem:asphericitycriterion} for a functor, will turn out pretty
much formal, and we'll finally be able to state a new version of the
``key result'' about test functors $i:A\to\Cat$, with this time twice
as many equivalent formulations of the same property. On n'arr\^ete
pas le progr\`es!
\bigbreak
\presectionfill\ondate{31.3.}\par
% 48
\hangsection[A journey through abstract homotopy notions (in terms
\dots]{A journey through abstract homotopy notions
\texorpdfstring{\textup(}{(}in terms of a set
\texorpdfstring{$W$}{W} of ``weak
equivalences''\texorpdfstring{\textup)}{)}.}\label{sec:48}%
It's time now to develop some generalities about homotopy classes of
maps, the relation of homotopy between objects of a modelizer, and the
corresponding notion of contractibility. For the time being, it will
be enough to start with any category $M$, endowed with a set
$W\subset\Fl(M)$ of arrows (the ``weak equivalences''), satisfying the
mild saturation assumptions \ref{it:37.a}\ref{it:37.b}\ref{it:37.c} of
par.\ \ref{sec:37} (p.\ \ref{p:59}). On $M$ we'll assume for the time
being that there exists (at least one) homotopy interval
$\bI = (I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$ in $M$ (loc.\ sit.) which implies also
that $M$ has a final object, which I denote by $e_M$ or simply $e$,
and equally an initial element $\varnothing_M$. I'm not too sure yet
whether we'll really need that the latter be strict initial element,
as required in the definition of a homotopy interval on page
\ref{p:59} (it was used in the generalities of pages \ref{p:59} and
\ref{p:60} only for the corollary on the Lawvere
element\ldots). Whether or not will appear soon enough! I'll assume it
till I am forced to. To be safe, we'll assume on the other hand that
$M$ admits binary products.
Let\pspage{99} $X,Y$ be objects of $M$, and
\[ f,g: X\rightrightarrows Y\]
two maps in $M$ from $X$ to $Y$. One key notion constantly used lately
(but so far only when $f$ is an identity map, and $g$ a ``constant''
one -- which is equally the case needed for defining contractibility)
is the notion of an \emph{\bI-homotopy from $f$ to $g$}, namely a map
$X\times I\xrightarrow h Y$ making commutative the diagram
\[\begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(O.base),sep=small]
& X\times I \ar[dd,"h"] & \\
X \ar[ur,"\id_X\times\delta_0"] \ar[dr,swap,"f"] & &
X \ar[ul, swap, "\id_X\times\delta_1"] \ar[dl,"g"] \\
& |[alias=O]| Y &
\end{tikzcd}.\]
Let's first restate the ``\hyperref[lem:homotopylemma]{homotopy lemma}'' of page \ref{p:60}
in a slightly more complete form:
\begin{homotopylemmareformulated}\label{lem:hlr}
Assume $f$ and $g$ are \bI-homotopic. Then:
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*),font=\normalfont]
\item\label{it:48.hlr.a}
$\gamma(f)=\gamma(g)$, where
\[\gamma: M \to W^{-1}M=H_M\]
is the canonical functor
\item\label{it:48.hlr.b}
If $f$ is a weak equivalence, so is $g$ \textup(and conversely of course,
by symmetry of the roles of $\delta_0$ and $\delta_1$\textup).
\item\label{it:48.hlr.c}
Assume $f$ is an isomorphism, and $g$ constant -- then $X\to e$
and $Y\to e$ are $W$-aspheric.
\end{enumerate}
\end{homotopylemmareformulated}
It is important to notice that the relation ``$f$ is \bI-homotopic to
$g$'' in $\Hom(X,Y)$ is not necessarily symmetric nor transitive, and
that it depends on the choice of the homotopy interval
$\bI=(I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$. Thus the symmetric relation from
$\bI$-homotopy is $\check\bI$-homotopy, where $\check\bI$ is the
homotopy interval ``opposite'' to \bI{} (namely with
$\delta_0,\delta_1$ reversed). The example we are immediately
interested in is $M=\Cat$, with $W=W_\Cat$ the usual notion of weak
equivalence. A homotopy interval is just an aspheric small category
$I$, endowed with two \emph{distinct} objects $e_0,e_1$. (The
condition $e_0\ne e_1$ just expresses the condition $e_0\sand
e_1=\varnothing$ on homotopy intervals -- if it were not satisfied,
\bI-homotopy would just mean equality of $f$ and $g$\ldots) For the
usual choice $I=\Simplex_1=(e_0\to e_1)$, an \bI-homotopy from $f$ to
$g$ is just a morphism between functors $f\to g$ -- the $\bI$-homotopy
relation between $f$ and $g$ is the existence of such a morphism, it
is a transitive, and generally non-symmetric relation. If we take $I$
to be a category with just two objects $e_0$ and $e_1$, equivalent to
the final category, an \bI-homotopy between $f$ and $g$ is just an
isomorphism from $f$ to $g$ -- the \bI-homotopy relation now is both
transitive and symmetric, and it is a lot more restrictive than the
previous one. If we take $I$ to be the barycentric
subdivision\pspage{100} of $\Simplex_1$, which can also be interpreted
as an amalgamated sum of $\Simplex_1$ with itself, namely
\[I = \begin{tikzcd}[baseline=(A.base),row sep=-7pt,column sep=small]
e_0 \ar[dr] & \\ & |[alias=A]| e_2 \\ e_1\ar[ur] &
\end{tikzcd},\]
an \bI-homotopy from $f$ to $g$ is essentially a triple $(k,u,v)$,
with $k:X\to Y$ and $u:f\to k$ and $v:g\to k$ maps in $\bHom(X,Y)$;
this time, the relation of \bI-homotopy is symmetric, but by no means
transitive. Returning to general $M$, it is customary to introduce the
equivalence relation in $\Hom(X,Y)$ generated by the relation of
\bI-homotopy -- we'll say that $f$ and $g$ are \emph{\bI-homotopic in
the wide sense}, and we'll write
\[ f \Isim g,\]
if they are equivalent with respect to this relation. As seen from the
examples above (where $M=\Cat$), this relation still depends on the
choice of the homotopy interval \bI. Let's first look at what we can
do for fixed \bI, and then how what we do depends on \bI.
If $f$ and $g$ are \bI-homotopic, then so are their composition with
any $Y\to Z$ or $T\to X$. This implies that the relation $\Isim$ of
\bI-homotopy in the wide sense is compatible with compositions. If we
denote by
\[\Hom(X,Y)_\bI\]
the quotient set of $\Hom(X,Y)$ by the equivalence relation of
\bI-homotopy in the wide sense, we get composition between the sets
$\Hom(X,Y)_\bI$, and hence a structure of a category $M_\bI$ having
the same objects as $M$, and where maps from $X$ to $Y$ are
\bI-homotopy classes (in the wide sense -- this will be understood
henceforth when speaking of homotopy classes) of maps from $X$ to $Y$
in $M$. Two objects $X,Y$ of $M$, i.e., of $M_\bI$ which are
isomorphic as objects of $M_\bI$ will be called
\emph{\bI-homotopic}. This means also that we can find maps in $M$
(so-called \emph{\bI-homotopisms } -- namely $M_\bI$-isomorphisms)
\[ f:X\to Y, \quad g:Y\to X\]
such that we get \bI-homotopy relations in the wide sense
\[gf \Isim \id_X,\quad fg \Isim\id_Y.\]
We'll say $X$ is \emph{\bI-contractible} if $X$ is \bI-homotopic to
the final object $e_M=e$ of $M$ (which visibly is also a final object
of $M_\bI$), i.e., if $X$ is a final object of $M_\bI$. In terms of
$M$, this means that there exists a section $f$ of $X$ over $e$, such
that $fp_X$ is \bI-homotopic in the wide sense to $\id_X$ (where $p_X$
is the unique map $X\to e$). In fact, if there is such a section $f$,
any other section will do too.
From the homotopy lemma \ref{it:48.hlr.a} it follows that the canonical
functor\pspage{101} $M\to W^{-1}M=H_M$ factors into
\[ M \to M_\bI \to H_M = W^{-1}M,\]
and from \ref{it:48.hlr.b} it follows that if $f,g: X\rightrightarrows Y$
are in the same \bI-class, then $f$ is in $W$ if{f} $g$ is, hence by
passage to quotient a subset
\[ W_\bI \subset \Fl(M_\bI)\]
of the set of arrows in $M_\bI$, namely a notion of weak equivalence
in $M_\bI$. It is evident from the universal property of $H_M$ that
the canonical functor $M_\bI\to H_M$ induces an isomorphism of
categories
\[H_{M_\bI} = W_\bI^{-1}M_\bI \tosim H_M=W^{-1}M.\]
It's hard at this point not to expect that $W_\bI$ should satisfy the
same mild saturation conditions as $W$, so let's look into this in the
stride (even though I have not had any use of this so far). Condition
\ref{it:37.b} of saturation, namely that if $f,g$ are composable and
two among $f,g,gf$ are in $W$, so is the third, carries over
trivially. Condition \ref{it:37.a}, namely the tautological looking
condition that $W$ should contain all isomorphisms, makes already a
problem, however. It is OK though if $W$ satisfies the following
saturation condition, which is a strengthening of condition
\ref{it:37.c} of page \ref{p:59}:
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*'),start=3]
\item\label{it:48.cprimeone}
Let $f:X\to Y$ and $g:Y\to X$ such that $gf\in W$ and $fg\in W$,
then $f,g\in W$.
\end{enumerate}
This condition \ref{it:48.cprimeone} carries over to $M_\bI$
trivially. This suggests to introduce a strengthening of the ``mild
saturation conditions'', which I intend henceforth to call by the name
of ``saturation'', reserving the term of ``\emph{strong saturation}''
to what I have previously referred to occasionally as ``saturation''
-- namely the still more exacting condition that $W$ consists of
\emph{all} arrows made invertible by the localization functor $M\to
H_M=W^{-1}M$, or equivalently, by some functor $M\to H$. Thus, we'll
say $W$ is \emph{saturated} if{f} it satisfies the following:
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*')]
\item\label{it:48.aprime}
For any $X$ in $M$, $\id_X\in W$.
\item\label{it:48.bprime}
Same as \ref{it:37.b} before: if two among $f,g,gf$ are in $W$, so
is the third.
\item\label{it:48.cprime}
If $f:X\to Y$ and $g:Y\to X$ are such that $gf,fg\in W$, then
$f,g\in W$.
\end{enumerate}
Each of these conditions carries over from $W$ to a $W_\bI$ trivially.
I can't help either having a look at the most evident exactness
properties of the canonical functor $M\to M_\bI$: Thus one immediately
sees that for two maps
\[f,g : X \rightrightarrows Y=Y_1\times Y_2,\]
with components $f_i,g_i$ ($i\in\{1,2\}$), $f$ and $g$ are
\bI-homotopic in the wide sense if{f} so are $f_i$ and $g_i$ (for
$i\in\{1,2\}$). The analogous statement is valid for maps into any
product object $Y=\prod Y_i$ on a finite set of\pspage{102} indices. The
dual statement so to say, when $X$ is decomposed as a sum $X=\coprod
X_i$, is valid too, provided taking products with $I$ is distributive
with respect to finite direct sums. Thus we get that $M\to M_\bI$
commutes with finite products, and with finite sums too provided they
are distributive with respect to multiplication with any object (or
with $I$ only, which would be enough).
The notion of \bI-homotopy in the wide sense between
$f,g:X\rightrightarrows Y$ can be interpreted in terms of strict
$\bI'$-homotopy with variable $\bI'$, as follows, provided we make
some mild extra assumptions on $(M,W)$, namely:
\begin{enumerate}[label=\alph*)]
\item\label{it:48.a}
(Just for memory) $M$ is stable under finite products.
\item\label{it:48.b}
$M$ is stable under amalgamated sums $I \amalg_e J$ under the final
object $e$ ($I$ and $J$ endowed with sections over $e$).
\item\label{it:48.c}
If moreover $I$ and $J$ are aspheric over $e$, then so is $I\amalg_e J$.
\end{enumerate}
Conditions \ref{it:48.b} and \ref{it:48.c} give a means of
constructing new homotopy intervals \bK, by amalgamating two homotopy
intervals \bI{} and \bJ, using as sections of \bI{} and \bJ{} for
making the amalgamation, either $\delta_0$ or $\delta_1$, which gives
four ways of amalgamating -- of course we take as endpoints of the
amalgamated interval, the sections over $e$ coming from the two
endpoints of \bI{} (giving rise to $\delta_0$ for \bK) and \bJ{}
(giving rise to $\delta_1$ for \bK) which have not been ``used up'' in
the amalgamation. Maybe the handiest convention is to define
\emph{the} amalgamated interval $\bI lor \bJ$, without any ambiguity
of choice, as being
\[ \bI \lor \bJ = (I,\delta_1^\bI) \amalg_e
(J,\delta_0^\bJ)\qquad
\parbox[t]{0.33\textwidth}{\raggedright endowed with the two
sections coming from $\delta_0^\bI:e\to I$, $\delta_1^\bI:e\to
J$,}\]
and defining the three other choices in terms of this operation, by
replacing one or two among the summands \bI, \bJ{} by the ``opposite''
interval $\check\bI$ or $\check\bJ$. The operation of amalgamation of
intervals, and likewise of homotopy intervals, just defined, is
clearly associative up to a canonical isomorphism, and we have a
canonical isomorphism of intervals
\[ (\bI\lor \bJ)\check{\phantom{\mathrm i}} \simeq \check\bI \lor \check\bJ.\]
I forgot to check, for amalgamation of homotopy intervals, the
condition \ref{cond:HIb} of page \ref{p:59}, namely $e_0 \sand e_1 =
\varnothing_M$ (which has not so far played any role, anyhow). To get
this condition, we'll have to be slightly more specific in condition
\ref{it:48.b} above on $M$ of existence of the relevant amalgamations,
by demanding (as suggested of course by the visual intuition of the
situation) that $I$ and $J$ should become subobjects of the
amalgamation $K$, and their intersection should be reduced to the
tautological part $e$ of it. More relevant still for the use we have
in mind is to demand that those amalgamations should commute to
products by an arbitrary element $X$ of $M$.\pspage{103} This I'll
assume in the interpretation of $\Isim$ in terms of strict
homotopies. Namely, let
\[\Comp(\bI)\]
by the set of all homotopy intervals deduced from \bI{} by taking
amalgamations of copies of \bI{} and $\check\bI$, with an arbitrary
number $n\ge1$ of summands. Thus we get just \bI{} and $\check\bI$ for
$n=1$, four intervals for $n=2$, \ldots, $2^n$ intervals for $n$
arbitrary. It is now immediately checked that for $f,g$ in
$\Hom(X,Y)$, the relation $f\Isim g$ is equivalent to the existence of
$\bK\in\Comp(\bI)$, such that $f$ and $g$ be \bK-homotopic (in the
strict sense).
\begin{remark}
The saturation conditions
\ref{it:48.aprime}\ref{it:48.bprime}\ref{it:48.cprime} on $W$ are
easily checked for the usual notion of weak equivalence for
morphisms of topoi, and hence also in the categories \Cat{} and in
any topos, and therefore in any category \Ahat{} (where it boils
down too to the corresponding properties on $W_\Cat$, as
$W_A=i_A^{-1}(W_\Cat)$). Thus it seems definitely reasonable
henceforth to take these as the standard notion of saturation
(referring to its variants by the qualifications ``mild'' or
``strong''). On the other hand, the stability conditions
\ref{it:48.a}\ref{it:48.b}\ref{it:48.c} on $(M,W)$ are satisfied
whenever $M$ is a topos, with the usual notion of weak equivalence
-- the condition \ref{it:48.c} being a consequence of the more
general Mayer-Vietoris type statement about amalgamations of topoi
under closed embeddings of such (cf.\ lemma on page \scrcommentinline{?}). The same
should hold in \Cat, with a similar Mayer-Vietoris argument -- there
is a slight trouble here for applying the precedent result on
amalgamation of topoi, because a section $e\to C$ of an object $C$
of \Cat, namely an embedding of the one-point category $e=\Simplex_0$
into $C$ by choice of an object of $C$, does not correspond in
general to a closed embedding of topoi. (In geometrical language, we
get a ``point'' of the topos \Chat{} defined by $C$, but a point
need not correspond to a subtopos, let alone a closed one\ldots)
This shows the asphericity criterion for amalgamation of topoi, and
hence also for amalgamation of categories, has not been cut out with
sufficient generality yet. As this whole $\Comp(\bI)$ story is just
a digression for the time being, I'll leave it at that now.
\end{remark}
More important than amalgamation of intervals, is to compare the
notions of homotopy defined in terms of a homotopy interval \bI, to
the corresponding notions for another interval, \bJ. Here the natural
idea first is to see what happens if we got a morphism of intervals
(compatible with endpoints, by definition)
\[ \bJ\to\bI.\]
It\pspage{104} is clear then, for $f,g\in\Hom(X,Y)$, that any
\bI-homotopy from $f$ to $g$ gives rise to a \bJ-homotopy; hence if
$f$ and $g$ are \bI-homotopic, they are \bJ-homotopic, and hence the
same for homotopy in the wide sense. We get thus a canonical functor
\[ M_\bI \to M_\bJ\]
which is the identity on objects, entering into a cascade of canonical
functors
\[ M \to M_\bI \to M_\bJ \to H,\]
where $H=H_M=W^{-1}M$ can be viewed as the common localization of $M,
M_\bI, M_\bJ$ with respect to the notion of weak equivalences in these
categories. We may view $M_\bJ$ as a closer approximation to $H$ than
$M_\bI$. There is of course an evident transitivity relation for the
functors corresponding to two composable morphisms of intervals
\[ \bK\to\bJ\to\bI.\]
\begin{remark}
In order to get that $\Isim$ implies $\Jsim$, it is sufficient to
make a much weaker assumption than existence of a morphism of
intervals $\bJ\to\bI$ -- namely it suffices to assume that the two
sections $\delta_i^\bI: e\to I$ are \bJ-homotopic. More generally,
let $\sim$ be an equivalence relation in $\Fl(M)$, compatible with
compositions and with cartesian products (this is the case indeed
for $\Jsim$), and let $\bI=(I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$ any object $I$ of
$M$ (not necessarily aspheric over $e$) endowed with two sections
over $e$, such that $\delta_0\sim\delta_1$. Then the interval \bI{}
gives rise to an equivalence relation $\Isim$ in $\Fl(M)$, whose
definition is quite independent of $W$ -- and a priori, if $f\Isim
g$ and $f\in W$, this need not imply $g\in W$. However, the
condition $\delta_0\sim\delta_1$ implies immediately that the
relation $\Isim$ implies the relation $\sim$. When the latter is
$\Jsim$, we get moreover that $W$ is the inverse image of a set of
arrows in $M_\bI$, i.e., $f\Isim g$ and $f\in W$ implies $g\in W$.
\end{remark}
An interesting particular case is the one when we can find a homotopy
interval $\bI_0$ in $M$, which has the property that for any other
homotopy interval \bI{} in $M$, its structural sections satisfy
\[\delta_0^\bI \Izsim \delta_1^\bI.\]
This implies that the homotopy relation $\Izsim$ is implies by all
other similar relations $\Isim$, i.e., it is the coarsest among all
relations $\Isim$. We may then view $\bI_0$ as a
``\emph{fundamental}'' or ``\emph{characteristic}'' \emph{homotopy
interval} in $M$, in the sense that the relation $f \Wsim g$ in the
sense below, namely existence of a homotopy interval \bI{} such that
$f \Isim g$, is equivalent to $f\Izsim g$, i.e., can be check using
the one and unique $\bI_0$. In the case of $M=\Cat$, we get readily
$\Simplex_1$ as a characteristic homotopy interval.\pspage{105} More
specifically, if $\delta_0,\delta_1:e \to I$ are two sections of an
object $I$ of \Cat, i.e., two objects $e_0,e_1$ of the small category
$I$, then these are $\Simplex_1$-homotopic if{f} $e_0,e_1$ belong to the
same connected component of $I$, which is automatic if $I$ is
$0$-connected, and a fortiori if $I$ is aspheric. This accounts to a
great extent, it seems, for the important role $\Simplex_1$ is playing
in the homotopy theory of \Cat, and consequently in the whole
foundational set-up I am developing here, using \Cat{} as the basic
``modelizer''.
It is not clear to me for the time being whether it is reasonable to
expect in more or less any modelizer $(M,W)$ the existence of a
characteristic homotopy interval (provided of course a homotopy
interval exists). This is certainly the case for the elementary
modelizers met so far. Presumably, I'll have to come back upon this
question sooner or later.
We'll now see that the set of equivalence relations $\Isim$ on
$\Fl(M)$, indexed by the set of homotopy intervals \bI, is ``filtrant
d\'ecroissant'', namely that for two such relations $\Isim$ and
$\Jsim$, there is a third ``wider'' one, $\Ksim$, implied by both. It
is enough to construct a \bK, endowed with morphisms
\[ \bK\to\bI,\quad \bK\to\bJ\]
of homotopy intervals. Indeed, there is a universal choice, namely the
category of homotopy intervals admits binary products -- we'll take
thus
\[ \bK = \bI \times \bJ,\]
where the underlying object of $\bK$ is just $I\times J$, endowed with
the two sections $\delta_i^\bI \times \delta_i^\bJ$ ($i\in\{0,1\}$).
As usual, we'll denote by $\Wsim$ or simply $\sim$ the equivalence
relation on $\Fl(M)$, which is the limit or union of the the
equivalence relations $\Isim$ -- in other words
\[f\Wsim g\quad\text{if{f} exists \bI, a homotopy interval in $M$,
with $f\Isim g$.}\]
For $X,Y$ in $M$, we'll denote by
\[ \Hom(X,Y)_W\]
the quotient of $\Hom(X,Y)$ by the previous equivalence relation. This
relation is clearly compatible with compositions, and hence we get a
category $M_W$, having the same objects as $M$, which can be equally
viewed as the filtering limit of the categories $M_\bI$,
\[ M_W = \varinjlim_\bI M_\bI,\]
where we may take as indexing set for the limit the set of all \bI's,
preordered by $\bI\le\bJ$ if{f} there exists a morphism of intervals
$\bJ\to\bI$ (it's the preorder relation opposite to the usual one on
the\pspage{106} set of objects of a category\ldots).
We now get canonical functors
\[ M \to M_\bI \to M_W \to H,\]
where $H$ can again be considered as the common localization of the
three categories $M$, $M_\bI$ (any \bI), $M_W$ with respect to the
notion of weak equivalence in each. It is clear that the set of weak
equivalences in $M_W$, say $\overline W$, is saturated provided $W$
is. Also, the canonical functor $M\to M_W$ commutes with finite
products, and also with finite sums provided formation of such sums in
$M$ commutes with taking products with any fixed element of $M$.
A map $f:X\to Y$ is called a \emph{homotopy equivalence} or a
\emph{homotopism} (with respect to $W$) if it is an isomorphism in
$M_W$, namely if there exists $g:Y\to X$ such that
\[gf\Wsim\id_X, \quad fg\Wsim\id_Y.\]
This implies that $f$ and $g$ are weak equivalences. If such an $f$
exists, namely if $X$ and $Y$ are isomorphic objects of $M_W$, we'll
say they are \emph{$W$-homotopic}, or simply \emph{homotopic}. This
implies that there exist weak equivalences $X\to Y$ and $Y\to X$, but
the converse of course isn't always true. If $Y$ is the final object
$e_M$, we'll say $X$ is \emph{$W$-contractible} (or simply
\emph{contractible}) instead of $W$-homotopic to $Y=e$. In case there
exists a characteristic homotopy interval $\bI_0$, all these
$W$-notions boil down to the corresponding $\bI_0$-notions considered
before.
\begin{remark}
If occurs to me that in all what precedes, we never made any use
really of the existence of a homotopy interval! The only notion we
have effectively been working with, it seems to me, is the notion of
``weak homotopy interval'', by which I mean a triple
$\bI=(I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$ satisfying merely the condition that $I$
be aspheric over $e$ (which is the condition \ref{cond:HIc} on page
\ref{p:59}). Such an \bI{} always exists of course, we need only
take $I=e$ itself! In case however an actual homotopy interval (with
$\Ker(\delta_0,\delta_1)=\varnothing_M$) does exist, to make sure that
the notion of $W$-homotopy obtained by using all weak homotopy
intervals is the same when using only actual homotopy intervals, we
should be sure that for any $I$ aspheric over $e$, any two sections
$\delta_0,\delta_1$ of $I$ over $e$ are $W$-homotopic in the initial
meaning. This is evidently so when $M=\Cat$ and $W=W_\Cat$ (indeed,
it is enough that $I$ be $0$-connected, instead of\pspage{107} being
aspheric), and in the case when $M$ is one among the usual
elementary modelizers. The question of devising notions which still
make sense when there is no homotopy interval in $M$ isn't perhaps
so silly after all, if we remember that the category of
semi-simplicial face complexes (namely without degeneracies) is
indeed a modelizer, but it hasn't hot a homotopy interval. However,
for the time being I feel it isn't too urgent to get any more into this.
\end{remark}
% 49
\hangsection{Contractible objects. Multiplicative intervals.}\label{sec:49}%
I would like now to elaborate a little on the notion of a contractible
element $X$ in $M$, which (I recall) means an object, admitting a
section $e_0:e\to X$, such that the constant map
\[c = p_Xe_0 : X\to e\to X\]
is homotopic to $\id_X$, i.e., there exists a homotopy interval $I$
such that $\id_X\Isim c$ (\bI-homotopy in the wide sense).
If $X$ is contractible, then the constant map $c:X\to X$ is a weak
equivalence (as it is homotopic to $\id_X$ which is) and hence by the
saturation condition \ref{it:48.cprime} (in fact the mild saturation
condition \ref{it:37.c} suffices) it follows that $p_X:X\to e$ is a
weak equivalence. In fact, one would expect it is even universally so,
i.e., that $p_X$ is an \emph{aspheric} map, as a plausible
generalization of the homotopy lemma \ref{it:48.hlr.c} above (which we
have used already a number of times as our main asphericity criterion
in elementary \Ahat\ldots). The natural idea to prove asphericity of
$p_X$, namely that for any base change $S\to e$, the projection
$X_S=X\times S\to S$ is a weak equivalence, is to apply the precedent
criterion to $X_S$, viewed as an element of $M_{/S}$. As the base
change functor commutes with products, it is clear indeed that for two
maps $f,g:X\rightrightarrows Y$ in $M$, \bI-homotopy of $f$ and $g$
will imply $\bI_S$-homotopy of $f_S$ and $g_S$, with evident
definition of base change for an ``interval''. On the other hand,
asphericity of \bI{} over $e$ implies tautologically asphericity of
$\bI_S$ over $S$, the final object of $M_{/S}$, which is all we need
to care about to get the result that $X_S\to S$ is a weak
equivalence. (The condition \ref{cond:HIb} on homotopy intervals is
definitely misleading here, as it would induce us to put the extra
condition that the base change functor is compatible with initial
elements, which is true indeed if $\varnothing_M$ is strict, but here a
wholly extraneous condition\ldots)
Thus \emph{$X$ contractible implies $X$ aspheric over $e$}. It is
well-known that the converse isn't true, already for $M=\Sssets$, or
$M=\Spaces$ with the usual notions of weak equivalences, taking
aspheric complexes which are not Kan complexes, or ``aspheric'' spaces
(in the sense of singular cohomology) which are not CW-spaces. The
same examples show, too, that even a good honest homotopy interval
need not be contractible,\pspage{108} contrarily to what one would
expect from the intuitive meaning of an ``interval''. In those two
examples, the condition of getting two ``disjoint'' sections of the
aspheric $I$ over $e$ looks kind of trivial -- kind of unrelated to
the question of whether or not $I$ is actually contractible, and not
only aspheric. What comes to mind here is to look for \emph{contractible
homotopy intervals}, namely homotopy intervals
$(I,\delta_0,\delta_1)$ (including condition \ref{it:37.b} that
$\Ker(\delta_0,\delta_1)=\varnothing_M$) such that $I$ is not only
aspheric over $e$, but even contractible. Existence of contractible
homotopy intervals seems a priori a lot stronger than just existence
of homotopy intervals, but in the cases I've met so far, the two
apparently coincide. As a matter of fact, the first choice of homotopy
interval that comes to mind, in all those examples, \emph{is} indeed a
contractible one -- so much so that till the notes today I was
somewhat confused on this matter, and was under the tacit impression
that homotopy intervals are all contractible, and trivially so! But